preface
|| intro || 1
|| 2 || 3
|| 4 || 5
|| 6 || 7
|| 8 || 9
|| 10 || Epil
|| Biblio
Foundations
of Philosophy
6
The Notion of Judgment
For the desire to understand, once understanding is
reached, becomes the desire to understand correctly; in other words, the
intention of intelligibility, once an intelligibility is reached, becomes
the intention of the right intelligibility, of the true and, through truth,
of reality.1
Preliminary Exercises.
- Is it true that men are more intelligent than women? What information would
you need to answer this question? What definitions would you need to be clear
about to answer precisely? Does it matter for the answer whether you are a man
or a woman?
- Is it true that bodies will continue at rest or in motion unless interfered
with by other bodies? Can you prove it?
- Is it true that the ozone layer is being destroyed by
hydrofluorocarbons? Do
you know this or do you believe it?
- Which of the following lines is the longest?
- A relativist would say that we can pick our own truths; that there are no
absolutes; that everything is relative, a matter of choice. Is this a coherent
position?
1. Introduction
1. Outline. In part I we have been examining the activity
of direct and inverse insights of various kinds. We have appealed to dramatic
instances from history and hope that you were able to identify similar
experiences in your own intellectual development. It is not too difficult to
become aware of instances of direct understanding as insights can be quite
exciting, inspiring, illuminating, even brilliant.
However, direct and inverse insights in themselves give only
possibilities; the most brilliant of insights, of explanations, of hypotheses in
itself may or may not be correct, may or may not be true. Direct insight grasps
possibility; it is merely a bright idea. Whether it is anything more has to be
settled by a further question and a further insight, a reflective insight
leading to judgment. We passed over the question of verification and judgment in
our earlier chapters not because it was not important but in the interest of
doing one thing at a time. But direct insights can be so seductively attractive
that we fail to consider the further insight needed for verification.
We will begin this second part of the text by establishing
what we mean by judgment and reflective insight; this is an invitation to
discover how we actually reach conclusions which we hold to be true. We will
then summarize all that we have discovered about human knowing under the title
of cognitional structure, and put our position systematically and succinctly.
This is followed by a discussion of intellectual conversion where we consider
the dialectic involved in the unfolding of the process of knowing. We will then
tackle the critical problem, the so-called bridge between the subject and the
real world. If you are involved in the exercises and doing the personal
self-appropriation called for by this text you may have already some intimation
of the startling strangeness of the [194] world of understanding and knowing; it
is very different from what we expect and presume.
It would be difficult to over-emphasize the importance of
judgment. It is pivotal in the transition from thinking to knowing, from fiction
to fact, from bright ideas to verified ideas from the world of fantasy to the
real world. It is also crucial for the transition from subjectivity to
objectivity. It is not just important for a philosophy but for our life and our
culture. Just as modern philosophies are on the whole skeptical or neglectful of
truth, so also our culture in the public sphere is skeptical and negative
regarding the claims of truth. What is useful, what is successful, what gives
pleasure, what will sell, are readily valued, all too often displacing what is
true. One of our expectations of this text was that it would provide
foundations. It is in this chapter that we begin to lay the foundations for
knowing the difference between true and false, image and reality.
2. Thinking and Knowing. Direct and inverse insights are,
loosely speaking, about thinking; but now we are moving on to a consideration of
knowing. Knowing goes one step further than thinking. The additional step is the
reflective understanding leading to the judgment. In this chapter we will
consider the characteristics of a judgment and try to clear up the many
misunderstandings and misconceptions that there are about judgments. The
following chapter will consider the structure of reflective understanding which
is the insight that leads in to the judgment. The grounds for the judgment or
verification will be given in that chapter. Here we simply intend to get a clear
grasp of the difference between direct insight leading to definition and
reflective understanding leading to judgment. We find that the fundamental
difference between definition and judgment parallels the difference between
thinking and knowing. In judgment we are systematically introducing the idea of
correct or incorrect, true or false, fact or fiction. Our approach is still
self-appropriation. We now ask how do we make a true judgment; why do we make
false ones? One could appeal to all sorts of theories about truth, but for the
moment we want to see how the mind grasps the sufficiency of the evidence for a
true judgment. [195]
We can distinguish different modes in the operation of our
intelligence: an understanding mode and a reflective mode. In the first mode we
are doing a kind of brainstorming: what we are looking for are possibilities,
expanding the scope of our thinking and imagination, pushing back horizons,
expanding our vision. We open ourselves to new ideas, deliberately relaxing our
critical faculty, simply envisaging possibilities. This is a mode you might be
in as you begin a paper, or a sermon or an article.
But sooner or later this mode has to give way to the critical
reflective mode. This rich mass of new ideas, images and facts which you have
collected needs to be evaluated. Some of these are not true, some are not
relevant, some are offensive, others unsuitable. This is the reflective mode, a
sorting out, bringing criticism into play. For the most part in Part I we have
considered only the mode of direct understanding. Now we intend to appropriate
the more critical mode of judgment and reflective understanding.
3. Appropriation. For a variety of reasons appropriating
our judgments is quite difficult, much more difficult than becoming aware of our
direct insights. Very often the reflective insight is compacted into the direct
insight, coming so soon after the direct insight that it is very difficult to
separate the two. We ourselves have been guilty of this compacting as we have up
to now been pretending, for the sake of simplicity, that all insights are direct
insights.
The reflective insight is not as exciting as a direct
insight. It comes more quietly, peacefully, gradually. It is relatively easy to
get into the brainstorming mode and to recognize what we are doing; it is more
difficult to get into the critical mode and to become aware of what precisely is
meant by reflection. Reflective understanding can be a long drawn out process
and often it is difficult to pin down that crucial step from thinking into
knowing.
Sometimes judgment is confused with logic. There are many
systems of logic but most of them seem to be deductive, working from premises to
conclusions; lists of rules have to be learned to distinguish techniques which
are legitimate from those that are illegitimate. But the rules of logic are not
the rules of thought. We [196] are concerned with the rules of thought; how do
we, in fact, in everyday life, reach a conclusion which we hold to be true and
are prepared to defend strenuously. We are not concerned for the moment with
logic but with the processes by which people actually reach conclusions that
they know to be true: what is rational process?
There are many senses to the little word "is". 'A
unicorn is an animal with one horn' and 'the horse is in the garden' both use
the copula. But one is expressing a definition, the other a judgment of fact.
Sometimes the many uses of the one copula hide the fact that we are moving from
possibility to actuality, from thinking to knowing; there may be no grammatical
difference whatever between a proposition entertained as a possibility and the
same proposition firmly maintained as true.
It is easy enough to make judgments. We are making them every
day. They can be simple judgments, that the bus is late, it is raining, the
computer is down, Fred is not in the office; or they can be more complicated
like there is a mistake in this calculation, this witness is lying, the economy
is getting out of recession, etc. What is difficult is not making judgments but
objectifying the process of making judgments. There are very few epistemologies
which differentiate between the understanding mode and the critical mode,
between formulation and judgment. Few of them have adverted to the actual
experience of making judgments. So often they have been uncritical theories
about what knowing should be, rather than an appropriation of what knowing
actually is. Surely if we want to know about judgments we should start with the
experience of making a judgment, start with the data and move on to the
explanation. The key to our procedure is this appeal to your own experience, to
identify and verify everything we say about judgment.
4. Historical Note. Aristotle spoke of judgment as a
synthesis of terms. His approach in the Categories was very grammatical:
a predicate is affirmed or denied of a subject. This was ambiguous as the
judgment could still be on the level of definition or supposition. Most of his
examples in the Analytics were simply suppositions: Socrates is sick,
etc. This is a proposition; it can be assumed to be true, but it only becomes a
judgment if it is affirmed to be true.
Aquinas spoke of judgment as compositio or divisio,
namely, composing or dividing. He inherited the Aristotelian terminology. But it
is quite clear that he has a good grasp of the difference between a proposition
as a synthesis of terms and a judgment as positing or affirming of the truth of
that synthesis. Just as Aquinas had identified the act of direct understanding
in active intellect enlightening the phantasm so that the form is received
immaterially in the possible intellect; so he grasped that reflective
understanding evaluates the grounds for the judgment going back to the senses,
the definition and first principles and so affirms or denies in the judgment. A
judgment is not only a synthesis of terms but a personal affirmation of that
synthesis as true. His analogy for the processions in the Trinity was based on a
grasp of this rational procession from evidence to affirmation in a judgment.2
None of the three founders of modern philosophy were able to
distinguish between statements considered as possibilities and judgments
affirmed to be true. Descartes states explicitly, "..I judged that I could
take it to be a general rule that the things we conceive very clearly and very
distinctly are all true,.."3 He takes 'clear
and distinct' as his criterion of what is true: whatever is clear and distinct
is true, if it is confused and ambiguous it is not true. But this totally
conflates two distinct activities of understanding and makes them one. In trying
to solve mathematical puzzles you may get clear and distinct ideas but they are
often totally wrong. The confused relative insights of description may or may
not be correct. There is a further question after the direct insight. Descartes
was so fascinated with the brilliance of clear and distinct ideas that he did
not realize that a further question arises. No matter how fascinating an idea,
to be affirmed as true requires another act of the mind.
Kant examines the logical structure of a judgment very
closely. He distinguishes a priori and a posteriori judgments, analytic and
synthetic judgments; in this he was examining the relation between the predicate
and the subject. His epistemology was an attempt to justify the possibility of
synthetic a priori judgments. But he misses the point that a proposition is one
thing but a personal affirmation of the truth of the proposition is something
further. He missed the distinction between the proposition as a synthesis of
terms and [198] positing that synthesis as true. His work, Critique of
Judgment was about aesthetic judgments of beauty.
Locke and Hume were also incapable of distinguishing between
propositions as logical constructs and propositions as affirmed to be true.
Their successors, the linguistic analysts systematically rule out of court any
consideration of mental acts and so distinguishing possibilities from truths is
eliminated. Truth is consigned to logic.
The three great traditions of modern philosophy totally
missed the basis for any consideration of truth in the judgment and that is at
least one reason for the failure of contemporary philosophies to deal adequately
with the topic. Not having a sound foundation it is then difficult to defend
against the relativists, skeptics and deconstructionists. The topic is almost an
embarrassment. One of the great achievements of Lonergan is the retrieval and
articulation of this distinction.
5. What judgment is NOT. The word 'judgment' is used in
many contexts with various meanings. To prevent misunderstanding let us briefly
indicate what we do not mean by judgment. 'Judgment' is not being used in the
sense of a moral judgment. The word often has the sense of the Last Judgment, a
moral judgment of guilty or not guilty, the judgment of history, etc. There are
indeed value judgments but these are best dealt with in ethics and religious
studies. We are using the word judgment in a morally neutral sense as an
affirmation or denial, of what is simply true or false.
Nor are we using 'judgment' in the sense as a quality of a
person. Sometimes we say that a person is a good judge of character; that he has
good judgment in business matters; that a man of skill has good judgment born of
long experience at his trade. We praise the judgment of a general who knows when
to attack and when to retreat; of a football player who knows when to pass and
when to go on his own; of a sculptor who is a good judge of perspective.
Judgments are not choices or decisions. We do make choices
and decisions; usually we do so in terms of a scheme of values, what we consider
to be important or desirable; that process is best studied and objectified in
ethics or religious studies. However, it is very common for people to think that
we can decide what to hold to be [199] true at the level of judgments of fact,
science and philosophy. Freedom of choice is a legitimate value but does it
extend to choosing what we will consider to be true or false? Do we have that
awesome power to make something to be true by our free choice? A philosophy
department might offer a variety of philosophical positions to study; a
supermarket offers a variety of brands of toothpaste; do we have the same kind
of choice in the two cases?
By 'judgment' we do not mean aesthetic judgment. There is a
field of aesthetics where judgments can be passed on paintings, poetry,
literature, sculpture, etc. But we are dealing with the intellectual pattern of
experience. There is an analogous truth in the field of aesthetics where you can
refer to an authentic poem, a true picture, etc. To say that a poem is true, and
a proposition is true, is to shift from the aesthetic pattern of experience to
the intellectual. In philosophy we are in the intellectual pattern of experience
where the criterion for truth is different from that of aesthetics.
2. Different Kind of Question
To identify the experience of making a judgment of truth, the
first thing to note is that the question which leads to the judgment is
different from the one that leads to a direct insight.4
When we were dealing with direct insights we considered all sorts of questions
like what? why? where? who? how often? etc. All of these questions are seeking
further information relevant to a direct understanding. But there is also a
series of questions that arise which are different in intention and tone. These
are questions like, Is it so? Is it correct? Is it true? Is it real? Does it
exist? Is he really sick? Does he really have cancer? Did he really do that?
etc.
What is to be noted about these questions is that they
anticipate a different type of answer: a Yes or No answer. They are not looking
for further information, or further understanding; they are looking for
affirmation or denial. A question already specifies the kind of answer that will
satisfy it; if I ask, 'what time is it?' and you answer 'Yes', you have not been
of much help. If I ask, 'Is it really true?' and you answer, 'five o'clock,'
then again something is wrong. So the first characteristic of a reflective
understanding is that it is asking a [200] fundamentally different kind of
question and sending the mind off on a different kind of search than the
question for direct insight. It is extremely important to note this difference
because it is the question that specifies what the relevant insight is going to
be.
We distinguish, then, questions for intelligence and questions
for reflection. Questions for intelligence are questions asking for further
information, questions seeking a clearer understanding or distinction, questions
that are looking for further content. The usual questions of where? when? why?
how many? how often? what is the weight? what is the distance? what is the
answer? what is the required correlation? what is the required word? what is the
formula? what is the definition? are all questions for intelligence. They cannot
be answered with a yes or no; they are looking for more data, more content,
clarifications, further relevant information, further direct understanding.
Questions for reflection are questions that are not looking
for further content but are seeking a simple yes or no answer, is it so?
Questions for reflection are oriented towards an act of reflective understanding
that will normally lead to the judgment, an affirmation or denial.
Every direct insight will normally be followed by a
reflective insight leading to a judgment. A direct insight gives us a
possibility, a correlation, a bright idea, a hypothesis or a possible
explanation, but normally we are only interested in possibilities as a halfway
house to verifications and truths. So if we give it a chance the question will
arise, is the hypothesis true? Can the bright idea be also the correct idea? Can
the correlation be verified in the data and in all the data? Can the hypothesis
be confirmed and raised to the status of a verified explanation?
Concomitant with every direct insight there is a question
that arises for reflection: is this correct? is it true? is it so? Our critical
thinking in solving mathematical or word puzzles involves a constant shifting
from insights into possibilities, to judgments as to whether they are correct or
not. Most of the possibilities we reject as they do not solve the puzzle; until
eventually we hit on the final possibility and find that this is correct. There
is something very fundamental about this constant shifting from possibilities to
[201] reflection; it is a kind of hypothetical-deductive method in the sense of
constantly throwing up hypotheses only to sort them out and reject many of them
because they do not satisfy the criteria set in the question. Plato likened
thinking to a person having a conversation with himself. Thinking is a constant
stream of ideas, images, examples, direct insights and inverse insights; the
mind does engage in this forward movement towards a conclusion. There is a
constant oscillation from the mode of seeking new possibilities to the critical
mode of asking is this possibility the right one.
Direct insight must precede reflective insight. To ask is it
so? presupposes that we have understood what 'it' stands for. If we are not
clear, then we have to ask what do you mean by so and so. If you are in an
argument about whether men are more intelligent than women, at some point you
will have to ask, what do you mean by intelligent. Psychologists define
intelligence differently; some allow for culturally determined differences some
don't; some define intelligence as purely theoretical, some as practical, some
as intuitive; does intelligence increase with education? etc. Direct
understanding presents content for the reflective insight. If the direct
understanding is vague, confused or ambiguous, then the judgment will be
similarly ambiguous. Many a philosophy discussion hinges on the phrase, 'Well,
it depends on what you mean.' Further clarifications and definitions or
divisions bring us back to the level of direct understanding, but again the
question will arise, 'is it true?' and we are back to the critical level of
judgment.
The answer to the question for reflection can be Yes or No or
anything in between, such as, probably, possibly, very likely, etc. Or it can be
of the kind, I do not know, I am not sure, I have not sufficient evidence for
that, etc. There are very few judgments of which we can be absolutely,
unequivocally and eternally certain. There is a wide range of probabilities from
the highest probability, which we can consider as virtually certain, to the
lowest range of bordering on the merely possible. But all of these are
legitimate and coherent answers to the question for reflection.
Note that the question for reflection arises spontaneously,
automatically, instinctively; it is hard to avoid it, difficult to stifle or
ignore it. It is only in certain limited contexts that we can ignore [202]
questions for reflection, such as when we are writing novels, composing poetry,
creating a work of art, brainstorming, or playing games. But in scholarship,
science, philosophy or any of the areas of knowing, it arises spontaneously and
we normally are not satisfied until we reach what we consider to be true. Our
questioning is purposive; we are seeking knowledge; there is a question of true
and false, correct or incorrect; we want to find the true and correct solution.
If we jump to conclusions on the basis of insufficient evidence, we realize that
our colleagues will reveal the shortcomings of our research and show that we are
wrong.
We can teach children the contents of correct judgments but
we do not need to teach them the art of asking questions for reflection. There
comes a time in the development of the mind of the child when he/she begins to
evaluate the stories they are being told by adults. Fairy tales, Santa Claus,
and stories about monsters that eat you are slowly examined and found wanting.
There is no evidence for them; all the available evidence is against them. We
give content to the judgments of the growing child, but the basic process of
evaluation in terms of true and false is not learned but emerges spontaneously.
Even children can and do ask Plato's question, 'is it really real?'
3. Affirming or Denying
The essential characteristic of the judgment is this quality
of affirmation or denial. There is a fundamental difference between considering
a hypothesis as a possibility and uttering it as a personal conviction; this
difference lies in the activity of understanding which produces now one, now the
other. This happens within human minds; it is invisible. The data for the
distinction are the data of consciousness not the data of sense. In this section
we examine this experience of affirming or denying as products of the activity
of intelligence.
A proposition is a statement or a definition. A proposition
can be a mere object of thought or it can be the content of a judgment. The old
Latin phrase put it non asserendo sed recitando, not affirming but
reciting. You can teach the philosophy of Kant merely as an [203] object of
thought. A teacher could go to great pains to explain clearly and accurately
Kant's position. But it may not be the position of the teacher who will
constantly remind the students that this is Kant's position, not my own. In that
context, Kant's philosophy is simply an object of thought, a complicated system
of terms and ideas; but it is not necessarily affirmed as a personal conviction.
A Kantian, on the other hand, is not only teaching what Kant taught, but is also
identifying himself with this position; to criticize Kant is to criticize him;
for this teacher it is not only an object of thought but also of personal
affirmation and conviction; it is true.
A proposition can be a mere supposition, a definition, an
object of thought, a synthesis of concepts, a consideration, a hypothesis.
Direct insight yields possibly relevant hypotheses which can be produced at will
by the simple act of defining or supposing. Logicians often deal with
propositions such as 'Socrates is sick', 'all Irishmen eat porridge', 'Louis the
fourteenth is the king of France'. These are mere objects of thought. Sometimes
for the purposes of the argument they are supposed to be true; meaning that if
they are true, then these conclusions follow; if they are false, other
conclusions follow. But in logic such propositions are not usually affirmed
personally to be really true. Mere objects of thought can be neither true nor
false; the categories do not apply. Ideas are products of direct understanding;
they are suppositions, concepts, theories, explanations, propositions; they can
be brilliant, new, inspiring, appropriate, complicated, or crude. But the
question 'is it true?' only arises in the context of reflection.
So, as well as being an object of thought the proposition can
be affirmed as true or denied as false; it can be the content of a judgment.
Then it has a completely different status. It has moved from thinking to
knowing; it is subject to a new criterion. Mere thoughts cannot be either true
or false, but judgments are affirming or denying and must be either true or
false.
Another way of identifying the nature of the judgment is to
note that judgment adds no new content to the hypothesis other than the simple
yes or no; it simply removes the question mark from the interrogation. Is John
really sick? becomes, John is really sick. There is a long process of reflection
which makes this transition [204] possible. The judgment does not add any new
content to the interrogation. It adds the yes or no of affirmation or denial.
That is the proper content of the judgment. The material element of the
proposition, the terms and what they refer to can be called the borrowed content
of the judgment. But the judgment adds no new ideas, information, data, or
definitions, other than the affirmation or denial.
The judgment adds only affirmation or denial. But that is no
small thing. From being a mere object of thought a proposition becomes an
affirmed content of our knowledge. We are no longer merely thinking or
supposing, we are knowing what is and what is not. This is what divides fact
from fiction, the real world from the world of fantasy, chemistry from alchemy,
astronomy from astrology. This element is crucial. What could be more important
than whether something is true or false?
A book is a whole series of words and sentences expressing
propositions. One can read the book and understand the propositions without
passing judgment on their truth or falsity. The ideas, suggestions, arguments,
evidence, conclusions of the book can be entertained as simply interesting. It
is a further step and a big one to take sides for or against the conclusions.
Then we either agree or disagree. That is a judgment.
Judgments happen only in minds. Marks on paper can represent
and express the judgments of individuals but the event, the happening is only in
a mind. Judgments are invisible. We have access to these affirmations and
denials because we can shift our awareness from the objects to the activities.
Defining and judging are quite different activities. If you do not advert to the
data of consciousness you will never be able to distinguish possibilities from
affirmations.
4. Taking a Personal Stand
There is an element of personal responsibility that enters
with the judgment, which is not there when we are merely considering or
supposing. As long as we are merely thinking of possibilities we are still
sitting on the fence and can go either way. But once we have [205] made the
judgment we have come down on one side or the other and are committed to the
judgment. It is our judgments that make us what we are as reasonable human
beings. The person is involved from the level of experiencing to the level of
understanding to the level of reflective understanding issuing in judgment. A
whole series of activities finally issue in the judgment.
Lonergan often quotes de la Rochefoucauld to the effect that,
'Everybody complains of his memory but no one of his judgment.' We feel that we
are not responsible for our memory. Either we have a good memory or a bad
memory; it is a God-given gift to his chosen ones. We are not embarrassed if we
forget someone's name and we blame our memory as an excuse. But in some way we
are responsible for our judgments. We take personal responsibility for the
judgment because it is a commitment. We made the judgment on the basis of the
evidence. We could have looked for more information, we could have asked for
clearer definitions, we could have asked further relevant questions, we could
have introduced appropriate qualifications and reservations. We apologize for
our bad memories; we do not apologize for our judgments.
We cannot be excused for mistakes of judgment; we are held
responsible. A meteorologist is expected to know his trade and his judgments are
expected to be accurate within a given degree of probability. The judgment is a
free act and if there is not sufficient evidence, we should reply, 'I do not
know.' Besides the absolute affirmation or denial there is a range of
possibility or probability in between. We are responsible for assessing the
evidence and enunciating a judgment which correctly mirrors the weight of the
evidence as probable, highly probable, or certain.
Strangely enough we cannot avoid making judgments; we have to
take a stand. Paradoxically, even sitting on the fence involves taking a stand.
Consider the philosopher who says, 'Judgments are not important, we can do
without them,' but in the very act he is making a judgment. Or consider the
skeptic who says, 'I know nothing,' yet he is positing a judgment. Or the
relativist who claims that everything is relative, except this statement that
everything is relative. There is an inescapability about judgments; we have to
take a stand, even if our stand is to run away. [206]
5. Completes the process of Knowing
When you posit an affirmation, the entire series of
activities involved in the knowing process come to a term. When you have solved
and checked a mathematical or a chess puzzle you know that your solution is
correct and you simply move on to other matters. The problem no longer holds
your interest, you have exhausted it, it is no longer challenging, it is in fact
boring. All the activities of questioning, searching for images, looking,
drawing, considering, remembering, defining, exploring, testing, checking,
reviewing, reflecting, come to a full stop when we posit the judgment. The
judgment sweeps everything into one affirmation or negation. A unit of knowledge
is added to our habitual store and we move on to other matters.
We are at a stage now when we can clearly distinguish three
levels of cognitional process. It will help to define the judgment if we
give a summary of these three levels here; the levels will be defined in greater
detail in the chapter on Cognitional Structure where a helpful diagram is also
presented.
Our concentration at the beginning of this text was upon
direct understanding. This level of cognitional operations is characterized by
the activities of defining, distinguishing, considering, forming hypotheses,
classifying, identifying, explaining, relating, correlating, counting,
measuring, calculating, supposing, conceiving, etc. We identified the
characteristics of this level in chapter two. Understanding gives us a possibly
relevant hypothesis, a bright idea, a set of concepts or definitions, which may
or may not be correct. This we will refer to as the second level of
cognitional operations.
But understanding presupposes something that is to be
understood. It presumes a level of presentations, of data, of the given. It
presupposes the level of experience where data are given but are not yet
understood. There has to be a content to the act of understanding; we have to
understand something. What is the something, where does it come from? Examine
your own activity of knowing and you will find that the matter, the content
comes from [207] the senses, from memory or from imagination. This we will call
the first level of experience.
But understanding gives only possibilities; it is only
thinking, and a further question arises as to whether this thinking is correct
or not. So we move into the reflective mode when we are weighing the evidence,
checking the results, studying the link between the conclusion and the premises,
examining the reasoning, etc. This is the level of reflective understanding that
issues in the judgment. When the judgment is made the whole process comes to a
halt; it has reached a term; there is a closure. This we refer to as the third
level of cognitional process. It presupposes the other two and would be
impossible without them, but does go beyond them to add its particular singular
contribution to the process of knowing.
6. Contextual Aspect of Judgment
Judgments occur in developing minds and within a context of
many other judgments on which they depend in various ways. A judgment can rarely
stand in glorious isolation. We have already identified the context of
description and explanation: judgments of description will presume the knower as
the center of reference and all descriptive judgments will be coherent with that
assumption. Explanation will assume the context of relating things to one
another. If you do not distinguish the two contexts endless confusion can
follow. Higher viewpoints will depend on a previous context of lower judgments.
Preliminary confused judgments will lead gradually to further clarifications in
more refined judgments.
Our own individual judgments today depend on our previous
judgments and on the whole context of questions, insights, formulations, etc.
that is our intellectual history. The expert in any subject is the one who has
set up such a context of judgments and experience that he can deal expeditiously
and immediately with any new problem or question within his field. Habits of
inquiry and research are built up over years and the competent person
immediately knows how to cope. Alternatively if we have not built up the context
of the expert or if we have not developed the habits of the intellectual pattern
of experience, we will suffer for it now as we [208] struggle to exclude
extraneous interference and clarify what remains confused in our mind.
The content of our present judgments may be in conflict.
There may be an apparent conflict between judgments of common sense and those of
explanation. There may be ambiguity in the use of terms. It is the task of logic
to establish the coherence or incoherence of different judgments within the one
system. If logic cannot reconcile our various judgments then we must suspect
that some one or other of them is wrong and we have to sort them out.
Our judgments also look to the future. We realize how little
we understand and how much remains to be done. Our knowing is dynamic: a
restless devotion to the task of adding increments to a merely habitual
knowledge.
7. Belief and Tradition
1. The Notion of Belief 5. If
you examine the convictions that you hold to be true and the reasons for holding
them to be true, you will probably find that most of your judgments are not
immanently generated but are some kind of belief. What we have been talking
about so far is immanently generated knowledge, knowledge that we personally
have acquired: we have experienced and understood the grounds for these
judgments. But if we examine most of what we judge to be true in history,
geography, politics or economics, even the empirical sciences, we find that we
have not personally experienced the grounds of our judgments and we accept them
as true on the authority of a teacher, author, publisher, photographer, editor,
reporter, and so on.
It is common to contrast Science with Belief, on the
assumption that all science is immanently generated knowledge and that belief is
on the borderline of superstition. But if you have learned any empirical science
you notice see that most of the time you take the author's or professor's word
for what he says. You do crucial experiments, but you do not find it necessary
to repeat every experiment and calculation. Belief as we are using the term is
as much part of the collaboration of the scientific enterprise as of any other
discipline. [209]
We understand belief as accepting something as true, not on
the basis of personally experienced evidence but on the ground of a trustworthy
source. The source can be an individual, a friend, an announcer, a scientist, a
professor; or it can be a medium, a radio channel, a periodical, a historical
document, a newspaper; or it could be a community, a tradition or culture.
The ground for belief is the communicability of truth. When
we reach a judgment we find that the conditions for the truth of the judgment do
not depend on us. The judgment is true independently of us. Truth, then, can be
communicated without necessarily communicating the immanent reasons for the
truth; it can be accepted as true on the basis of our own grasp of the
conditions for its truth and also on trust that someone else has grasped these
conditions and is honestly communicating his results to us.
2. What belief is NOT. We are NOT using the term belief
as equivalent to opinion. Translations of Plato usually use opinion and belief
as the two forms of sense knowledge that Plato held not to be true knowledge at
all. 'Belief' is used in a similar kind of way in the contemporary analytic
school. We are using the word as a technical term, which is generally in line
with common usage but which differs from many philosophical schools.
We are NOT using it in a religious sense. The word is,
perhaps, most commonly invoked in theology and religious belief, but our usage
of it is purely neutral and secular and has as much to do with empirical science
as with theology. Belief is part of the human collaboration in the enterprise of
knowing in all fields, because of specialization and the simple fact that we
cannot repeat all the experiments and research that has produced the results
which we take for granted in order to move ahead.
We are NOT using the word belief in any vague, loose,
commonsense meaning. In ordinary usage we often say 'I believe that is true',
but we do not always have the distinction that we are making here in mind. Here
we are giving that word a technical meaning and will try to use it always in
conformity with that definition. There is after all a big difference between the
person who has done the research and knows for himself, and the person who
listens to him lecturing and accepts what he reports as true. If we are [210]
serious about analyzing our judgments then we have to be clear on this
distinction and we have to introduce a critique of beliefs as a parallel track
to our critique of mistaken judgments.
3. Importance of Belief. To accept belief as a legitimate
activity in furthering knowledge rests on a judgment of value. What dangers are
we leaving ourselves open to and what are the values of accepting belief as a
reasonable part of human progress? When we examine the state of current
knowledge in the sciences and other areas we find that there is such an
accumulation of information, research results, books, documents, tables,
traditions, that if we were to start at the beginning to repeat all the
experiments and observations for ourselves then we would never reach even the
state of knowledge of the nineteenth century. Not only that but in any branch of
science where we wish to specialize, we still find that we are dependent on the
results and methods and instruments that pertain to other sciences. Are we to
check them all out before we proceed?
We are really faced with a choice between primitive ignorance
and accepting belief as a legitimate process that enormously facilitates
learning. Belief is a kind of short cut to the end. Instead of doing the
complicated calculations and experiments that may involve expensive materials,
we accept the results as true on the basis of the reports. Someone should check
out the results and repeat the calculations, but it is not necessary that
everyone repeat the process.
Not only are we dependent on the veracity of teachers and
authors but we also take it for granted that the instruments that we are using
have been made to correct specifications. We use slide rules, barometers,
thermometers, tables of logarithms, computer programs, calibrated scales and
measures of various kinds. We do not know that they are all made to
specifications unless we check for ourselves. We believe that they are correct
and only when things go wrong do we begin to suspect that maybe they are not up
to snuff.
Our knowledge of the past is gained through the study of
history, and our own immanently generated knowledge is limited to our short life
span. But history is mostly belief, not knowledge. We are trusting a whole
series of human sources that have communicated [211] what really happened. We
have the reports of eyewitnesses, the documents of state, the files of
government offices, the annals of armies, the diaries of individuals, and the
putting together of all these by a series of historians down the ages.
Our immanently generated knowledge of geography is limited to
what we have seen and heard; usually very little depending on our propensity to
travel. We depend on those who have seen, those who have reported the
conditions, those who have drawn the maps, measured the temperature and
rainfall, photographed, examined the flora and fauna, and published this in an
orderly and honest fashion.
Our conclusion must surely be that primitive ignorance is to
be avoided and that our participation in the development of human understanding
is much facilitated by reasonable belief. As we have explained, it is usually
quite reasonable to accept as true what we find in chemistry, geography and
history textbooks, not that this will be a totally blind acceptance. In normal
circumstances where appropriate checks and balances are in force, it will be
reasonable to believe and a bit paranoid to try to check everything for
yourself.
Belief can be quite certain. We do not distinguish judgments
and belief on the basis that judgments are certain and beliefs are slightly
dubious. We distinguish them on the basis of how we come to grasp the true as
true. In the case of judgments we rely on our grasp of the sufficiency of the
evidence for the conclusion; in beliefs we rely on the trustworthiness of the
source to communicate truthfully. But immanently generated knowledge as in the
empirical sciences may only reach a degree of probability, whereas a belief can
be quite certain. We can be quite certain that Ireland is an island. Few people
have actually personally traveled the coastline of Ireland to see for themselves
but yet the accumulation of witnesses attesting to the fact and reporting on
their limited experience is sufficient to accept the belief as certain. The
scientist is giving the best available opinion of his time; his conclusions are
probable rather than certain, as we explained earlier.
4. Critique of Beliefs. Just as there can be mistaken
judgments so also there can be mistaken beliefs. Beliefs are particularly prone
to wander from the truth because the evidence is detached from the conclusion.
To set up a critique of mistaken traditions we have to examine the source, the
communication and the message. We will give some brief indications as to what to
look out for in these different areas.
Source. You have to ask how trustworthy is the source,
how honest is the individual, would it be in his interest to lie or to slant the
truth. You look for evidence of bias, prejudice, self-interest,
self-glorification, etc. One suspects anyone who has much to gain by propagating
some information. You look for a neutral source, a non-involved observer,
someone who has nothing to gain for himself. You look for competence, for
someone who is in a position to know: you go to a doctor for information on
medicines and a meteorologist for information on the weather and not vice versa.
Communication. There can be quite a gap from the source
to the believer. There can be translation involved from one language to another
and that always involves an interpretation. There is the interpretation of the
text and of its importance and of its message. There are publishers, editors,
commentators, copiers, reporters, etc. Generally speaking, the farther we are
removed from the source, the more reason we have to be careful. Historical
studies of the Scriptures have revealed the work of editors, composers,
additions, and subtractions, changes of various kinds. Successive translations
can wander slowly from the original intention.
The message itself. Is it credible in itself? Does it fit
in with the context of what we already know? Is it reasonable in itself? A
legend reports how a monk interrupted Thomas Aquinas at his studies to report,
"Look," said the monk, "There is a cow flying." Aquinas
lumbered over to the window to see this great sight, whereupon the monk laughed
as he was only joking. Aquinas rejoined, "I prefer to believe that cows
could fly, than that a monk could tell a lie." By our education we build up
a context of what is possible, what is probable, what fits in what does not fit
in. We develop a sense of what is credible. If we are doubtful we check for
ourselves and do the crucial experiment. Alien abductions we judge to be
incredible; life on other planets we judge to be possible; black holes are now
asserted to probably exist; it is certain that there are millions of galaxies
besides ours. [213]
There are so many different circumstances that the only
general rule is to be ever intelligent and reasonable. Don't be gullible. Don't
be too credible. On the other hand it is reasonable to believe and we would be
unreasonable to want to see all the evidence for ourselves. Much of what we have
to say about judgments and reasonableness in the next chapter can also be
applied to beliefs.
5. Belief is assent. Belief requires a value judgment
about the value of believing in general, and also a value judgment that this
particular person is worth believing in this specific instance. Belief involves
an assent, a decision, a willingness to collaborate in the process of human
knowing and a willingness to accept this person’s word for this truth. Belief
differs from judgment in motive and origin. Judgment is motivated by the
strength of the evidence; but belief is motivated by the desire to collaborate
reasonably in the search for knowledge. The origin of a judgment is rational
necessity; the origin of a belief is a free and responsible decision to believe.
In conclusion, the notion of judgment raises the critical
question of whether we can know the truth or not. How do we move from thinking
to knowing, from possibilities to truth. Here we have simply identified the
activity of judging as the answer to the question for reflection, as affirming
or denying, as adding no new content, as knowing coming to a term. Our next
chapter deals with reflective insight which is the intervening act between the
question and the judgment.
Comments on Exercises.
- This is just to illustrate that judgment depends on definitions, in this
case the definition of intelligence. In some cultural systems boys will get
a better education than girls. Does this mean that they are more
intelligent? Also that bias will often enter into this area of research and
judgment. Why is so-and-so a feminist? Because she is a woman!
- The logical positivists sometimes have difficulty with this. How do you
prove it? How do you set up an experiment where there is a body that is NOT
interfered with by other bodies and then see what happens? It is simply not
possible. Our approach would be that the principle is verified indirectly
countless numbers of times in every experiment concerning movement and
gravity. The alternative hypothesis that bodies in motion will come to a
stop when they are not longer being pushed can easily be disproved. It is an
inverse insight.
- Most of us do not know the answer to this and have to believe those who
purport to know. There are vested interests at stake and it is legitimate to
ask who sponsored these studies and who carried them out. For most of us it
is a question of belief, not of immanently generated knowledge.
- Drawings can produce the appearance that one line is longer than another.
You can verify that they are the same size by using a ruler.
- The relativist says we cannot make true judgments, but what is the status
of his own judgments? This raises the question of coherence between saying
and doing discussed in the chapter on intellectual conversion.
End Notes
1. Bernard Lonergan, A Second Collection,
(London: Darton, Longman & Todd, 1974) 81.
2. See Bernard Lonergan, Verbum: Word and
Idea in Aquinas, Edited by Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran.
Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan, vol 2. (Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 1997) In this text Lonergan recovers the intellectualism of Aquinas
especially the distinction between definition chapter 1 and judgment in chapter
2. These two rational processes are the basis for the human analogy of the
Trinity, chapter 5.
3. Rene Descartes, Discourse on the Method
of Properly Conducting One's Reason and Seeking the Truth in the Sciences,
Discourse 4 (Penguin Books, 1968) 54.
4. Insight, chapter 9.
5. Insight, 725-739. This is
a rather technical treatment.
Go Back
|