|
|
Immediacy
and Mediation in Our Knowledge of Being: Some
Reflections on the Epistemologies of Emerich Coreth and Bernard Lonergan* Giovanni B. Sala, S.J.# Ten years ago Father Emerich Coreth,
professor of philosophy at the University of Innsbruck, published a large volume
on metaphysics[1] that soon was favorably
received, even among those who usually are not especially interested in
Neoscholastic philosophy. This work
had two obvious characteristics that were particularly important. The main
characteristic was the use of transcendental reflection, by which Coreth adopted
a movement of thought that began with Kant and continued through German Idealism
up to Husserl and Heidegger. He extended this method systematically, from the bare
formulation of the problem to a treatment of the entire traditional and modern
subject of metaphysics. The second
characteristic was that Coreth took as the privileged starting point for
metaphysical reflection the primordial human phenomenon of asking questions. Karl Rahner, in his “Geist im Welt”, had already
interpreted this questioning as asking about being. What was barely a hint in Rahner was elaborated
systematically and rigorously by Coreth. In fact, the first chapter of the Metaphysik,
which analyzes “the question and being”, seems to be the most original and
important chapter in the book. In
it, Coreth starts out from the question and, through a reductive and deductive
procedure, gradually ascends to the ultimate condition of the possibility not
only of the question, but of all human cognitive activity.
This ultimate condition is the pure pre-knowledge or horizon of being.
Two years later Father Bernard Lonergan
published his appraisal of the Metaphysik in this Journal[2].
This was so much more than an ordinary review that it was reprinted in
its entirety in the American edition of Coreth’s book.
Lonergan’s assessment was clearly positive, and it brings out the
importance of Coreth’s metaphysics in contemporary Scholastic thought.
Lonergan regards as decisive the fact that Coreth’s transcendental
analysis deals with an act (Vollzug, performance)—namely, the act of
questioning. This has important
consequences both with respect to Kantian phenomenalism and with respect to the
intuitionism of some Scholastic authors. Among
these Lonergan specifically considers Etienne Gilson. Kant looks for the a priori
conditions of the objects of knowledge—to be precise, the objects of
mathematics and Newtonian physics. As
a result, the a priori he reaches is in the formal or essentialist order:
the forms of sensibility and the categories of the understanding. Our striving for the unconditioned, for being in the
unqualified sense, is declared a transcendental illusion.
Coreth does not seek the formal conditions that make it possible to think
a universal and necessary object, but rather the conditions that make possible
our activity of asking questions. He
thus makes it clear that our striving for the unlimited, and therefore
unconditioned, is not at all an illusion. Rather, it is the primary condition that enters into all
questioning and, consequently, into all human answering and knowing.
This striving for the unconditioned constitutes our a priori
horizon of being. In this way, Coreth not only overcomes the closed inner area
of Kantian phenomenalism, but also makes unnecessary the a posteriori
perception of being in the data of sense that Gilson requires in order to pass
from the abstract concept of being to knowledge of the concrete extramental
existent. Lonergan thus agrees with Coreth that the
method and task of metaphysics is to mediate the immediate. According to Lonergan’s Insight[3],
this “immediate” that must be brought to the concept is, first of all, the
notion of being and the invariant structures through which it is realized;
according to Coreth’s Metaphysik it is the pure pre-knowledge or the
horizon of being. The two different
analyses thus come to the same conclusion. When I myself had occasion to study the Metaphysik,
I was particularly interested in the a priori character of the horizon of
being, and I came to the conclusion that Coreth had not recognized the full
truth about this apriority[4].
For he arrives through transcendental reduction at the horizon of being,
which he characterizes as an anticipation of the totality of the knowable, a
sketch (Entwurf) of the knowable, an outlining of the horizon of being
that constitutes our pure pre-knowledge of being. But then he asks, in § 13,
where we should seek the origin of this horizon.
And he answers that there must be a kind of knowing that possesses the
known, and possesses it precisely as being.
On the basis of that knowing, we have the sense of being in general and
are able to outline the horizon of the questionable as the horizon of being.
This knowledge that already possesses its known as being is our knowledge
of our very performance (Vollzugswissen) in asking the question, and it
takes place in consciousness. Therefore
an immediate experience of being is given in consciousness. In my previous essay I examined this issue
and tried to show that we certainly do know being in our consciousness and by
means of our consciousness, which is the subject’s experience of itself and
presence to itself. But this kind
of knowledge of being is exclusively anticipatory and heuristic, merely an
intellectually and rationally conscious desire to know.
To conceive the Vollzugswissen as [full] knowledge of oneself in
the act of questioning, so that we can base our search for further knowledge on
our assurance that we know this one existent, is to return to naïve realism à
la Gilson. Such a naïve realism
abstracts the concept of being from the sensible presentation, even though in
Coreth’s case the reality from which it is abstracted is internal. In his contribution to the First
International Lonergan Congress held in the spring of 1970, Coreth returned to
this problematic, referring mainly to Lonergan’s article “Metaphysics as
Horizon”[5].
In the present essay I propose to examine whether and to what extent
Coreth has accepted Lonergan’s interpretation of the apriority of the horizon
of being. Has he adopted for
himself the opposition to every form of perceptionism or intuitionism, and
thereby clarified the ambiguity I noted above? Or, rather, has he confirmed his tendency to naïve realism? In the following pages I shall try to
clarify that mediation of the immediate that both Coreth and Lonergan speak of.
What is immediate in our knowledge?
More exactly still, the immediate is opposed to what?
It thus is defined with respect to what?
This problem is relevant not only to epistemology, as is obvious, but
also to metaphysics. For only on
the basis of the conception of being as that which is intended by questioning,
by which we go beyond what is given to us in internal or external perception, is
it possible to work out an intellectual and rational conception of the real.
Now, when the objective pole of the horizon of being is recognized as
intrinsically intelligible, a whole series of theses receives its foundation:
the unification of the real in the all-embracing perspective of metaphysics, the
meaning of human life, and the possibility of moving intentionally from
proportionate being to the transcendent being we call God. I. – DUALITY OF SUBJECT AND
OBJECT OR UNITY OF BEING? In
Section II of his Lonergan Congress paper, Coreth examines the duality of
subject and object that he believes is implied in Lonergan’s approach to the
metaphysical question about being. I
would therefore like to clarify in what sense the subject is at the origin of
the horizon of being, and so is the subjective pole of this horizon. In order
to present Lonergan’s conception of the subject, Coreth refers to the first
two pages of Chapter XIII of Insight.
Now, the aim of that chapter is not at all to work out a doctrine of the
subject, but to work out the notion of the objectivity of our knowledge.
What does it mean to ask whether human knowledge is objective, or has
objective value? As the common use of that term indicates, for many it means
whether we are capable of knowing objects as they are, whether we are
capable of knowing realities other than ourselves just as they are in
themselves. Often, indeed, the
problem of objectivity is posed expressly as the question about what is other
than the subject, since the knowledge of the other is considered to cause the
difficulty. Hence the problem of
objectivity easily becomes the problem of the bridge. This metaphor indicates that what is being asked is whether
knowledge, an operation immanent in the subject, is able to reach as far as the
other, the object. Is it
transcendent in the peculiar sense of being knowledge of a reality beyond the
subject? Now, the
answer Lonergan gives to this in Chap. XIII of Insight consists, first of
all, in correcting the formulation of the problem.
The correct formulation asks whether or, rather, how we succeed in
knowing being. Therefore it
is a matter of clarifying through what process, and by virtue of what, our
knowledge arrives at being. It is
evident that the usual formulation of the problem of objectivity implies a
duality, the duality of subject and object.
Provisionally accepting this formulation, Lonergan responds by saying
that we know the object as being through rational judgment: x is.
But then he continues by saying that the same is true for the subject: It
too is known through a judgment. From
this simple equivalence it already follows that the real question does not
concern a problematic knowledge of the object in contrast to a non-problematic
knowledge of the subject. It
concerns the knowledge of being, whether it is the being that is the object or
the being that is the subject. Thus,
the initial duality is overcome in the higher unity of being[6]. Therefore,
if the correct formulation of the so-called problem of objectivity asks about
our knowledge insofar as it relates to being, it is not surprising that Lonergan
gives no special importance to our knowledge of that particular being that is
the subject. In other words, if, in
the context of the problem of objectivity, one asks whether we have objectively
valid knowledge of the subject, whether we know the subject as it is in itself,
Lonergan answers that this is nothing but a particular case of our knowledge of
being. Here, as in every other
case, we know being through rational judgment[7].
There are indeed differences, but they concern the point of departure,
the data, not the threefold structure of knowing or its completion in the
judgment[8].
Lonergan thus opposes those who deny objective knowledge of the subject
(e.g., Hume with his absolute phenomenalism or Kant, for whom the subject that
we know with objective validity is still only an appearance, just as external
objects are). But he also opposes those who privilege our knowledge of the
subject by interpreting it as a kind of immediate intuition, unlike our
“mediate” knowledge of objects. Hence,
it does not seem to me that in the discussion at the beginning of Chap. XIII of Insight
one can find a duality of subject and object that needs to be overcome by a
transcendental metaphysics[9].
There is a duality in the traditional question about objectivity, which
is explicitly about plurality, about knowledge of the object as other.
But Lonergan is not at all tied to this schema, and does not at all posit
this plurality as absolute[10],
i.e., as ultimate and irreducible. Rather,
he answers the question by situating the plurality within the common realm of
being. Thus the real issue becomes:
By what process do we reach knowledge of being?
This, I repeat, is not a matter of how a subject that starts out enclosed
in its subjectivity can reach something other than itself.
The movement of knowledge is from the unity of the subjective pole,
constituted by our intentio intendens [intention as intending], to the
unity of the objective pole, the universe of being.
This universe is gradually disclosed when true judgments of fact are
made. Both subject and object, and
also the intentio entis [intention of being][11],
are within the universe of being. It is in
Coreth’s position, rather, that I seem to discern a duality. In fact, after pointing out the origin of our knowledge of
being—a subject we shall return to later—he continues: “In so far as I ask
about being and thus have not taken hold of being totally in the performance of
my knowing, there appears a difference between performance and being.
More precisely, it is the difference between the being of one’s own
self-realisation and the being which transcends me and my performance, for
which—in asking about ‘other’—I must therefore first reach out”[12].
On the following page, though in a somewhat different context, Coreth
writes, “The first fundamental distinction that is established in every
performance of inquiring and knowing is the duality between me and the other,
between subject and Object”[13].
And farther on he speaks of the horizon of being “in which I relate
myself to other entities and distinguish myself from other existents, thereby
experiencing myself, however, immediately as an existent”[14].
It is certainly true that the difference between subject and object is
fundamental to the cognitional process. But
more fundamental and primary still is the difference between the intention of
being that stands at the origin of all our cognitional (intellectual) activity
and the true and proper knowledge of being that occurs in the judgment.
Thus, insofar as I am only an intending intention and not the whole of
being, I radically and always ask about being, but I do not always ask about the
other. Even when I ask about
myself, in order to know myself as something real, I ask about being.
In this case too I have to pass from a simple intending intention about
the data (the data of internal experience or consciousness) to knowledge of the
data in terms of being, which is the knowledge of myself as an existent[15].
One can
understand why Coreth tends to take as the primitive duality that of subject and
object. In the last of the three
quotations above, when he speaks of our movement toward the other within the
horizon of being, he adds: “thereby experiencing myself immediately as an
existent”[16].
I cannot see how this differs from the dualistic-Cartesian position,
according to which the problem of objectivity is how to pass from the “I”,
known as being in some immediate experience, to the object as other.
It is precisely to oppose this position that Lonergan illustrates the
principal notion of objectivity by affirming that the subject is known as an
existent in a true judgment, in the same way that the object and the difference
between subject and object are known in two other true judgments. In my
previous essay on the origin of the horizon of being, I analyzed the knowledge
of oneself as an existent. I showed
that this occurs according to the same structure as our knowledge of the
external world. In this sense, I
was denying, and still deny, an immediate experience of oneself as an existent.
For Lonergan, the belief in an immediate experience of being has no other
foundation than the myth of naïve realism.
From his perspective, it makes no great difference whether we are
speaking of the reality of the “I” or the reality of external things.
The only difference between the two is that between being conceived
primarily as “already out there now” and being conceived as “already in
here now”[17]. The
accusation that Lonergan understands being as objectivity[18]
probably originates in his statement, at the end of his review of Coreth’s Metaphysik,
that while metaphysics, as about being, equates with the objective pole of the
horizon, metaphysics as science does not equate with the subjective pole[19].
But first of all, it is obvious that metaphysics as science is not all
the knowledge that man has. It is
one particular science, albeit a fundamental and all-embracing one.
Now, if the subjective pole of the horizon of being is the intending
subject, it clearly does not exhaust itself in doing metaphysics.
The wise man, the philosopher of the Aristotelian tradition, is not the
mathematician, the economist, the historian, or the man of common sense.
But
there is a deeper meaning in Lonergan’s distinction.
To say that metaphysics embraces the entire objective pole of the horizon
of being does not mean that being is conceived as objectivity, in the sense of
something opposed to subjectivity[20].
It means that metaphysics deals with the whole of that to which our
intelligent and reasonable intentionality tends: being taken formally as being,
as the objective of our pure desire to know.
Being is “the great unknown that all our questions are about”[21].
Now, according to Lonergan there is so little opposition between being so
conceived and subjectivity that he writes, “This being of the questioning
questioner is the latent metaphysics from which explicit metaphysics is derived;
and in explicit metaphysics it is the primary analogate through which
other being as being is understood”[22]. The
subject already has and exercises in its intentional structures a latent
metaphysics that makes every man a seeker and a knower of being. But this subject has more in itself than a latent
metaphysics. The structures of our
intentionality are indeed the subjective pole of the universe of being. And beyond being there is nothing. Coreth’s analysis rightly limits itself to these
structures, since it is intended to be the systematic elaboration of
metaphysics, i.e., of the universe of being.
But, because of the polymorphism of its consciousness, the concrete
subject is also a latent anti-metaphysician.
For it is liable to personal, social, and historical biases in its own
intentionality; it is the source of what Lonergan calls counterpositions. Now, “The process… to explicit metaphysics is primarily a
process to self-knowledge”[23]
that heads toward the genuine subject giving free rein to its intelligence and
reasonableness and unhindered by any less pure desires.
Reaching the basis on which to establish and correctly develop explicit
metaphysics requires a critical analysis of the polymorphism of human
consciousness. This is the broader
consideration of the subjective pole that is not the task of metaphysics.
But one sees that it is not a matter of broadening the horizon: Beyond
the horizon opened by our intentionality, there is nothing.
It is rather a matter of passing from a more abstract to a more concrete
consideration of the subjective pole, from principle to fact.
This is what Lonergan alludes to at the end of his review of the Metaphysik.
And it is the existential aspect that is so evident in his analysis of
knowledge in Insight. II. – THE PURE
PRE-KNOWLEDGE OF BEING 1.The
subject as subject and the horizon of being Lonergan’s
conception of the subject as subject should not be sought solely or mainly in
his discussion of the principal notion of objectivity, but throughout Insight.
For this work, according to its author, is meant to be an “essay in aid
of a personal appropriation of one’s own rational self-consciousness”[24].
Insight is nothing but an extended effort to bring out what the
subject is, rather than what the subject does, i.e., the concrete structures
immanent and operative in its cognitive and volitional activities and in our
whole psychic life. What the subject is, and how, precisely as subject, it
contains the norms that make it open to the universe of being and of the good,
is the theme of Insight. The
difference between knowing oneself as object (discussed in the preceding
Section) and knowing oneself as subject is the difference between knowing
oneself as intelligible and as being, and knowing oneself simply as given in the
internal experience that is consciousness.
Hence, anyone who wants to find Lonergan’s position on the knowledge of
oneself as subject must go to Chap. XI of Insight, where consciousness is
discussed[25].
For consciousness is the only knowledge that we can have of ourselves as
subjects. It is not my purpose to
present Lonergan’s position on consciousness in this essay.
It is so broad and rich that it requires a far more extensive discussion
than is possible here[26].
It is enough if I indicate here the heading, so to speak, under which one
should look for the treatment of the subject as subject in Insight. Lonergan
is perfectly aware of the uneliminable subjectivity, mentioned by Coreth on his
pp. 39f, that is presupposed in each of our psychological activities and in
every objectivization of ourselves. Indeed,
he clearly distinguishes between the knowledge of oneself as subject (as
consciousness), which is pure experience and always remains experience, and the
knowledge of oneself that adds understanding and judgment to this experience,
and thereby moves from knowledge ex parte subiecti [on the side of the
subject] to knowledge ex parte obiecti [on the side of the
object]. Thus he clarifies in a
systematic way the type of consciousness that Coreth calls the “subject in its
self-realisation”. In an
article on cognitional structure, Lonergan concludes a section about the
difference between consciousness and self-knowledge with these words: “I have
been attempting to describe the subject’s presence to himself.
But the reader, if he tries to find himself as subject, to reach back
and, as it were, uncover his subjectivity, cannot succeed.
Any such effort is introspecting, attending to the subject; and what is
found is, not the subject as subject, but only the subject as object; it is the
subject as subject that does the finding. To
heighten one’s presence to oneself, one does not introspect; one raises the
level of one’s activity. If one
sleeps and dreams, one is present to oneself as the frightened dreamer. If one wakes, one becomes present to oneself, not as moved
but as moving, not as felt but as feeling, not as seen but as seeing.
If one is puzzled and wonders and inquires, the empirical subject becomes
an intellectual subject as well. If
one reflects and considers the evidence, the empirical and intellectual subject
becomes a rational subject, an incarnate reasonableness.
If one deliberates and chooses, one has moved to the level of the
rationally conscious, free, responsible subject that by his choices makes
himself what he is to be and his world what it is to be…
There exist subjects that are empirically, intellectually, rationally,
morally conscious. Not all know
themselves as such, for consciousness is not human knowing but only a potential
component in the structured whole that is human knowing.
But all can know themselves as such, for they have only to attend to what
they are already conscious of, and understand what they attend to, and pass
judgment on the correctness of their understanding”[27].
Now, it
is precisely in consciousness operating at the intelligent and rational level
that our horizon of being originates. Intelligent
and rational consciousness is the operation of our pure desire to know.
Because this desire is conscious, and conscious both intelligently and
rationally, it is, of itself and to itself, a notion of its proper objective,
which is being. Indeed, our horizon
or notion of being is this very desire, in its character as an intelligent
desire in search of the intelligible, and a rational desire in search of the
absolute. “The notion of being
is… the orientation of intelligent and rational consciousness towards an
unrestricted objective”[28].
Or again, “The pure notion of being is the detached, disinterested,
unrestricted desire to know”[29]. The
basic function of the notion of being, as that which makes all of our knowledge
knowledge of being, can be described as follows: “Spirit can pose the question
about being, and thus about the absolute, because spirit, present to itself in
its unrestricted openness, is already to itself a notion of the absolute.
If one does not already have, entirely a priori, this ‘sense’
of being, there are no data that can make one know it, and there is no teacher,
however capable, who can make one understand it.
One can ask about this or that being and on the basis of data, i.e., a
posteriori, one can manage to understand and know it.
But one cannot ask about being in general, being as the sense of being,
since it is itself the primary condition that makes possible every question and
all learning”[30]. Two
questions arise concerning the notion of being or the pure pre-knowledge of
being: (1) Whether it refers back to a foundation other than itself, and (2)
Whether it should be called an empty knowledge.
2. The
origin of the horizon of being I showed
at length in my preceding essay that the notion of being is the end point
reached by transcendental reflection on the conditions of the possibility of
knowledge. According to Coreth, the
horizon of being intrinsically constitutes each of our intellectual acts of
questioning and of knowing, since each such act is performed within the horizon
of being. When we have arrived at
this horizon, he says that “The question about the origin of the projection of
the horizon remains patently valid, even required”[31].
Now, Coreth continues, “This
question receives its answer only from the innermost nature of such a
performance, in which an identity of being and knowing is revealed, but at the
same time a distinction between being and knowing”[32].
This, so far as I understand it, means that our notion of being knows
being, but in such a way that all this knowledge only informs us that we do not
[explicitly] know being. It therefore enables and urges us to ask about being.
This brings out the kind of dynamic presence to ourselves at the
intellectual level that we call intelligent and rational consciousness, which
persists through every differentiation due to the diversity of data, diverse
patterns of experience we may be in, etc. Our
intellectual presence to ourselves has a sense or meaning, which is the sense of
being that is our primordial knowing of being.
But this sense is only anticipatory, only a projection (Entwurf) or
pre-knowledge (Vorwissen), only a sense of what it urges us to seek.
Because of it, we move on to the search for being, to the effective
knowledge and differentiation of beings within the realm of being. There is
a twofold function in our experience of ourselves: consciousness as the
experience of oneself, and consciousness as an operative intelligible[33].
Our pure pre-knowledge of being originates in consciousness; indeed, it
is that consciousness operating at the intellectual level.
When I say this, I am obviously referring to the second of these two
aspects that are discoverable in the single reality of consciousness.
But perhaps this point needs further explanation. My
thesis is that our anticipatory knowledge of being originates as the presence to
ourselves that is in each of our intelligent and rational psychological acts.
This presence is consciousness in its first aspect[34],
and it is identical with our pure pre-knowledge of being.
With and in these psychological acts, we experience ourselves.
This is the basis of our unity and continuity as subjects in the
multiplicity and variety of our acts. It
is the unity of the person. This
experience becomes differentiated and varied as soon as, through personal
actions but no less through social and historical influences, the individual’s
own world comes to be constituted within the ultimate and all-embracing horizon
of being. But in this presence to
ourselves or self-possession, the significance of which varies from one time to
another and from one person to another, a common and permanent trait is still
observable. It is that
consciousness is the realm in which occurs all our creating of sense (Sinngebung)
or projecting of sense (Sinnentwurf).
In technical terms, there is found the originary horizon that underlies
and makes possible the multitude of worlds.
I
experience myself in my psychological acts, so that I am able to make so-called
judgments of consciousness[35].
And I experience myself according to the particular world in terms of
which my personality is configured, so that, exceptional and pathological cases
aside, I have a coherent style of thinking, deciding, and acting.
The same is true for everyone. There
is a continuity even within the considerable variations that a single
personality may undergo, and there is a basis for understanding among
people—at least in principle—even if they belong to the most diverse
cultures or epochs. Why? Because in
every case the experience of oneself is the configuration and implementation of
the operative intelligible, the intelligent and rational intelligible, that is
the very essence of spirit. If, in
every case and for every configuration of personality, the experience we have of
ourselves at a spiritual level has the character of intelligence and
rationality, then in every case this experience is identical to the notion of
being. Hence,
Coreth is right to say that from the experience of myself I have anticipatory
knowledge of being, or project the horizon of being. The consciousness in which
being is unveiled is just the experience of oneself.
But he tends to interpret this experience of oneself as knowledge of
oneself, i.e., as knowledge of oneself as a reality or existent.
This tendency can be noticed in the Metaphysik, especially in §
13. “I know that the performance
of my questioning ‘is’; that it is posited in itself as an existent (als
seiend)… The performance is known
as being (als Sein)”[36].
“From the immediate experience of being and of the certainty of the
being of the performance, I know the being of the performance, and
thereby know being or the meaning of being in general.
This is the origin of our projecting of the horizon of being in
general” [37].
The same tendency is confirmed in his recent article: “What ‘being’
means, discloses itself in fact primarily, with greater immediacy, in the
actuality of one’s own self-realisation (self-performance)”[38].
And again: In the horizon of being I “experienc[e] myself immediately
as an existent”[39].
I would
like to try once again to clarify where, in my opinion, lies the difference
between Coreth and Lonergan in their conception of being. Coreth writes: “How could we project the horizon of being,
if we did not know ourselves as existents in being? The performance of asking and knowing [could] not reach
being, if it were not itself—as performance—being that realises itself and
in its performance knows itself”[40].
Certainly, the performance of the question is being.
Certainly, this is a particular performance, an operation, of that being
that is spirit. And what is spirit?
Human spirit is intentionality, a conscious dynamism toward the
universe of being and of the good. Now,
as conscious and operating, this intentionality knows itself.
But, and here is the point, this knowing is mere presence, mere
experience—the presence, I repeat, of an intelligent and rational
intentionality to itself. For our
intentionality, to be conscious of oneself (to know oneself experientially) as
intelligent and rational, is just the same as to know being in general by
anticipation. Now, Lonergan would consider it an error to call this
experiential knowledge of oneself, which coincides with the pure pre-knowledge
of being, the knowledge of oneself as an existent in being.
I think a more careful consideration of the notion of knowledge as
structure might lead Coreth to clarify the ambiguity that lies behind his
knowledge of the performance (Vollzugswissen) and his immediate
experience of oneself as being. The
notion of being does involve an identity of being and knowing, since this notion
is nothing but being in its self-transparency (das Sein in seiner
Gelichtetheit). But this does
not mean that the notion knows itself as being, i.e., with human knowledge in
the proper sense. It does not know
itself that way simply because human knowledge occurs only in the judgment, and
the notion of being is not a judgment. But
in order to operate, it does not need to be known in a judgment and thereby
become objectified. The notion of
being is that operative intelligible that is the spirit itself.
Now, given an adequate psychic development, and given the consciousness
of data—which ultimately are data of sense—this operative intelligible
operates intelligently and rationally. And
it operates independently of any objectivization, correct or not, that we manage
to make of it. To seek
the origin of our pure anticipation of being in some reality, for example in the
act of questioning known as a reality, is to radically undermine the a
priori that grounds and constitutes all human knowledge.
Obviously Gilson does not recognize an a priori when he writes
that we obtain the concept of being by abstraction from the data of sense[41].
But neither, it seems to me, does Coreth succeed in recognizing the a
priori when he writes in his Metaphysik: “From the immediate
experience of being and the certainty of the being of the performance, I know
the being of the performance and thereby know… the meaning of being in
general”[42]. But
perhaps what Coreth immediately adds to this can help us get to the root of his
position. He writes: “It is only
within the origin of the projecting of the horizon of being in general that it
is possible to ask about the other as being or to know the other
as being”[43].
If the problem of knowledge is posed as the problem of knowing the other
(as being, of course), then one is led to accept as obvious the knowledge of
oneself (again, as being). This knowledge would pose no difficulty, since it
supposedly would come about through an immediate intuition.
But if instead the problem is about knowing being, then one cannot simply
presuppose that I know myself (though now only an entity that questions) as
being and thereby have a sense of being that enables me to know everything else
as being. Thus, the question
returns: How do I know myself as being? Or,
in the words of Coreth, how do I know that “I am the one who asks and
that I am in the performance of the questioning?”
How do I know that “the performance of my questioning is?”[44]
It is no accident that, in the pages of his recent article where he
returns to this matter, Coreth mentions the knowledge of the other several
times. This is unexpected if one
recognizes that the problem is about our pure pre-knowledge, and our knowledge,
of being. Thus, for example, toward
the end of Section II he speaks of the horizon of being as that “in which I
relate myself to other entities”[45].
According to my interpretation, the horizon of being is the condition of
the possibility of knowing myself as being, just as much as it is the condition
of the possibility of knowing the other as being.
The
passage quoted earlier is significant for our problem about the origin of our
pure pre-knowledge of being: “What ‘being’ means, discloses itself in fact
primarily, with greater immediacy, in the actuality of one’s own self-realisation
(self-performance)”[46].
This “actuality” of one’s own performance recalls the ambiguity
that weighs on Coreth’s whole position with regard to the pure pre-knowledge
of being. Two senses of this notion
still have not been clearly distinguished, though it is necessary to choose
between them: (1)
Coreth may wish to say that in this self-realization we know ourselves as
being, and that as a result what “being” means discloses itself to
us. If so, we again have the naïve
realism that I criticized earlier. It
is naïve realism in the sense that our knowing ourselves as this reality
supposedly precedes the knowing that is our horizon of being. A fortiori, then, it precedes our implementing of the
cognitional structure by understanding and judging. (2)
Instead, he may wish to say that in the experience of ourselves (in
consciousness) at the intellectual level, our intentionality is revealed to us
(made present precisely as experienced) in its intelligent and rational
operativeness. And through that
experience[47]
we originally know what being means. If
so, Coreth is speaking the truth. But
in that case the qualification “with greater immediacy” seems entirely
superfluous and therefore misleading. For
it is only from this experience that we know what being means.
All that comes after, all explicit knowledge of internal or external
reality, does not contribute at all to our pure pre-knowledge of being.
The pure pre-knowledge of being is the ultimate condition that makes
human knowledge possible as knowledge in terms of being.
As such, it obviously cannot depend on the knowledge that it makes
possible. We must “be content”
with a knowing that is entirely anticipation or projection. In other words, the a priori of human knowledge is
nothing but the question[48], i.e., our pure desire to
know. 3. Is
the notion of being an empty knowledge? With
this, we have reached the second of the questions stated above: whether the pure
pre-knowledge of being, taken in the sense of Lonergan’s notion of being,
should be considered an empty knowledge. In
my view, there are two fundamental conceptions of the a priori: an
objective-content conception and a subjective-operative conception.
Under the first conception, the a priori is itself an object.
As Kant described it, it lies ready in our mind and is imposed or
superposed on the a posteriori content, which ultimately comes from
sensation. But under the second
conception, the a priori is not an object at all, and therefore is not a
part or content of what we know. It
is, rather, the subject’s operativeness, its capacity to make the content of
sensible representations intelligible, and then to ask about the absoluteness of
this intelligible[49].
Now, in the Critique of Pure Reason both of these conceptions are
present. They are in tension, but
in the end the objective-content conception prevails.
Hence, Kant is left with a conception of knowledge as creatively positing
reality, and with an idealist conception of the reality that is knowable to us. Now,
Lonergan’s broadly developed notion of being represents the passage from the
objective-content conception of the a priori to the subjective-operative
conception. According to
Lonergan, our a priori is primordial meaning in search of what is
intelligible, with a view to reaching what is.
Only an a priori so conceived is able to resolve the aporia
[intellectual block] that stands at the origin of Plato’s doctrine of ideas,
without falling into either the innatism of Plato or the a priori
categories of Kant. Meno, in the
dialogue that bears his name, formulates the aporia this way: If man
knows nothing before he starts to inquire, where can this inquiring begin?
And even if he encounters the truth, how can he recognize that it is the
truth?[50] No
learning starts with nothing at all. The
starting point for acquiring a specific item of knowledge at a certain stage in
our intellectual development is some objective knowledge we already have: a
certain scientific habitus [habit of mind], a mentality, or a complex of
particular items of knowledge. This previous knowledge can only be a relative a
priori. But if we ascend to the
original source of every instance of knowledge in every particular field, we no
longer find objective knowledge, knowledge of the objects either of nature or of
the human world. We find knowledge
that is entirely ex parte subiecti [on the side of the subject], i.e.,
subjective and heuristic.
There is
a passage in Insight that well illustrates what knowledge ex parte
subiecti means. This is not any
knowledge of objects, not even of that object that is the subject in the act of
questioning. From the description
given there, one sees that our notion of being is indeed a knowledge that is
entirely devoid of objects. But at
the same time, we can see how wrong it would be to call that knowledge empty or
senseless, something to which one ought to apply Hegel’s famous jibe about the
night in which all cows are black[51].
To illustrate our pure pre-knowledge of being, Lonergan turns to the
metaphor of obverse and reverse. And
he turns precisely to what man knows best, the products of his own labor.
In those products one can discern both an intelligible design and an
existence grounded in the labor that produced them.
“But before the design is realized in things, it was invented by
intelligence; before the sequence of productive operations was undertaken, it
was affirmed as worth while for some sufficient or apparently sufficient reason.
In the thing there is the intelligible design, but in the inventor there
was not only the intelligibility on the side of the object but also intelligent
consciousness on the side of the subject. In
the thing there is the groundedness that consists in its existence being
accounted for by a sequence of operations; but in the entrepreneur there was not
only the groundedness of his judgment in the reasons that led to it but also the
rational consciousness that required reasons to reach judgment.
Intelligence and intelligibility are the obverse and reverse of the
second level of knowing: intelligence looks for intelligible patterns in
presentations and representations… In
like manner, reasonableness and groundedness are the obverse and reverse of the
third level of knowing. Reasonableness
is reflection inasmuch as it seeks groundedness for objects of thought…
In man’s artefacts there are the reverse elements of the
intelligibility and groundedness, but there are not the obverse elements of
intelligence and reasonableness. The
obverse elements pertain to cognitional process on its second and third levels;
they do not pertain to the contents emergent on those levels, to the idea or
concept, to the unconditioned or affirmed; on the contrary, they characterize
the acts with which those contents are coupled and so they are specific
differentiations of the awareness of consciousness.
Clear and distinct conception not only reveals the intelligibility of the
object but also manifests the intelligence of the subject.
Exact and balanced judgment not only affirms things as they are but also
testifies to the dominance of reasonableness in the subject”[52].
To speak
of a notion that is intelligent and reasonable, and thus is a notion of the
objective to which it tends, is to stress the operative character of cognitional
process. To speak of a primordial
question in man is to affirm that human spirit is of itself meaning in search of
meaning. But the meaning we men are
endowed with is merely heuristic, merely anticipatory of reality.
This makes genuine inquiry possible, inquiry after something really
unknown and not just after something forgotten.
And it makes possible the recognition of reality once we have found it.
When, after a short or long inquiry, I arrive at knowledge, I am not
aware that I am comparing a pure idea that I have already contemplated with some
image of it that I have encountered in the spatio-temporal world.
I am not aware of a recognition on the basis of a cognition that I
already had. Rather, I have the
invincible persuasion that I am encountering this reality for the first time.
Nonetheless, there is a sense in which cognizing is recognizing.
It is the cry of surprise and satisfaction that breaks forth from a man
when he finally has found what he was looking for.
He previously knew nothing of the truth that now has shone on his spirit.
He did not know that his search was for this rather than for something
else. But now he knows.
How does he know? What is the criterion by which he examines everything in
order to accept this in the end and reject that?
The human spirit must have in itself, along with its total poverty, a
total capacity to discern and judge everything by placing it on the scale of
truth.
Rather
than say it is in the spirit, it would be more proper to say that this a
priori is the spirit itself. The
spirit is meaning for and to itself. The
spirit is what it means to itself; it is being in its luminousness, in its being
meaningful to itself. It is the
revelation and the constitution of the subject, according to a subjectivity that
is never objectifiable but that still, because of its awareness of its radical
indigence, tends toward the universe of being.
The meaning that is spirit itself is therefore a normative meaning for
the whole process of knowing. So
conceived, the notion of being is, if one likes, much less definite than the
Kantian a priori, which has the definiteness, i.e., the limitation, of an
object. But just for that reason
the notion of being is much more radical in its apriority and much more decisive
in its operativeness. It is as
all-embracing as our striving to know; it is as unlimited as the universe of
being. We are
again at the question I indicated above. The
peculiar kind of purely subjective knowledge I am trying to describe must indeed
be called empty, and therefore non-knowledge in every sense, if it is true that
the only content a cognitive act can have is its object.
But this assumption is false. In
one and the same cognitive act there is not only an object-oriented dimension,
but also a subject-oriented dimension [that is consciousness itself].
The latter makes our knowledge knowledge of being.
(Here I am considering knowledge above the level of sense.)
Hence, what Lonergan says about the notion of being points to what is
common, uneliminable, and primordial in the conscious dimension of every
intellectual act, i.e., its character of intelligence and rationality, by which
it designates and knows in advance that toward which it tends.
Therefore, the notion of being is indeed devoid of objects. But it is not devoid of content, unless one erroneously
assumes that the content of knowledge is coextensive with the object of
knowledge. On the contrary, a
consistent analysis will thoroughly work out the Aristotelian principle that
knowledge is unity, which in Scholasticism is expressed by the saying
“unumquodque cognoscitur secundum quod est actu [whatever is known is known
insofar as it is in act]”. Hence,
it will lead us to recognize that ultimately it is the object that is sublated
(i.e., negated and preserved at the same time) into the content ex parte
subiecti of knowledge. This
subjective content is the meaning that is the intelligence and rationality of
the pure desire to know. Ultimately,
the whole of reality is no longer just anticipated by intelligence and
rationality, but is that very intelligence and rationality, νόησις
νοήσεως [understanding of understanding].
The
conception of the pure pre-knowledge of being as nothing but our capacity to
pose intelligent and reasonable questions has its parallel in Insight in
the conception of reality as intrinsically intelligible.
For if the real is nothing but that which we intend with questions for
understanding and for reflection, and that which we know when we give a correct
answer to these questions, then the real must be said to be intrinsically
intelligible. “By intelligibility
is meant what is to be known by understanding.
By the intrinsic intelligibility of being is meant that being is
precisely what is so known or, in negative terms, that being is neither beyond
the intelligible nor apart from it nor different from it.
Now if by being one means the objective of the pure desire to know, the
goal of intelligent inquiry and critical reflection, the object of intelligent
grasp and reasonable affirmation, then one must affirm the intrinsic
intelligibility of being. For one
defines being by its intelligibility; one claims that being is precisely what is
known by understanding correctly; one denies that being is anything apart from
the intelligible or beyond it or different from it, for one’s definition
implies that being is known completely when there are no further questions to be
answered”[53]. From
this we see the importance of identifying our a priori, our pure
pre-knowledge of being, as the operative intelligible, as the intelligent and
reasonable obverse of that reverse that is the universe of being.
We are capable of knowing being because (1) we are endowed with a
conscious dynamism toward the absolute, a dynamism that is not bound by any
principle of immanence, since it is an unlimited capacity and exigence, (2) in
the critical reflection that precedes judgment, we are able to reach the
absolute in the form of the virtually unconditioned. If we do not manage to recognize such an obverse, the
question of the Meno remains in full force: How can we start out on the road to
reality—the process of knowing—if we don’t at all know what reality is?
And even given that we encounter reality, how can we recognize that it is
reality? The
solution to the Platonic aporia presented here is entirely based on the
thesis that we know reality through the operations of our cognitional structure.
Not, therefore, through the perceptions of the senses alone, but also
through the grasp of an intelligibility in what the senses have presented and
critical reflection on what we have understood, in the unity of a properly human
cognition. On the other hand, it is
not difficult to recognize the validity of this solution: Any opposing argument
could not help using the very criterion of reality we have formulated here. The
failure to recognize the purely heuristic-subjective nature of the a priori,
along with an irrational conception of the real[54],
leads to the typically Kantian position: Man understands, he conceives, and, in
some sense of the term, he judges. He
performs all these operations in a way consistent with their immanent norms.
But what does he thereby know of the real?
Nothing. The consistent,
intelligent and rational, and therefore true, implementation of our cognitive
dynamism is not a means of knowing reality.
And rightly so, if that reality ex hypothesi [by hypothesis] is
neither intelligible nor rational. But
one cannot admit the intrinsic intelligibility of the real if one does not
recognize that the real is nothing but what is known by answering questions for
intelligence and for reflection. Or
if one does not therefore recognize that the pure pre-knowledge of being, which
sets in motion and constitutes ab intrinseco [intrinsically] the whole
cognitional process, is nothing but the question.
The notion of being is thus the intelligent and rational desire to know
that grounds every “experience” of being, even our experience of that being
that is the subject itself.
III. --IMMEDIACY
AND MEDIATION IN OUR KNOWLEDGE OF BEING
1. The fundamental thesis of uncritical realism is intuitionism. At the
beginning of his paper, Coreth describes the positions of Gilson, Lonergan, and
himself concerning the knowledge of being, as follows: “For Gilson being is
the immediate; for Lonergan it is what is mediated or to be mediated; whereas
for me… it is at once ‘immediate and mediated’, i.e., it is mediated or
self-mediating immediacy”[55].
When he moves on to treat these positions in Section III, Coreth is
anything but decisive in rejecting Gilson’s intuitionism.
What interests him is the mediation of immediacy by transcendental
analysis. “Even when being has been immediately given to us, there
remains the task of mediating this immediacy transcendentally”[56].
After saying that he does not wish to contradict Gilson’s thesis
absolutely, he continues: “There is an intuitive element in
intellectual cognition; otherwise intellectual cognition would not even be
possible”[57].
In fact,
the problem is not to decide whether or not there is this intuitive element.
Neither in Metaphysics as Horizon nor in Insight does
Lonergan deny an intuitive element, as long as it is maintained this vaguely and
generally. Rather, the problem is
to say once and for all what this intuitive element is in which cognition is
ultimately supposed to consist, and whether its existence can be proven by
introspective analysis, since our cognitive acts are conscious. Coreth
believes he can demonstrate the existence of an intellectual intuition by
arguing that “otherwise intellectual cognition would not even be possible”.
This proof has force only if one presupposes what is to be proven, i.e.,
that ultimately the essence of cognition is intuition.
Kant would say, more consistently, and showing his cards more openly:
“Otherwise knowledge in general (überhaupt) would not be possible”. This is the direct consequence of the intuition principle (Prinzip
Anschauung) with which the Transcendental Aesthetic[58]
opens. Heidegger has formulated
this principle very aptly as follows: “In order to gain an understanding of
the Critique of Pure Reason, the following must, as it were, be hammered
in: Cognition is primarily intuition”[59].
Lonergan uncovers the basis of Coreth’s argument for an intellectual
intuition by exhibiting the fundamental thesis of naïve realism: “The analogy
of ocular vision reveals what intellectual activity must be like if it is to be
objective; it must be like seeing. Even
if introspection discovers no intellectual activity that resembles seeing, still
some such activity really must exist; for if it did not, then our intellectual
activity would be merely immanent”[60].
Lonergan
fully elaborates his answer to the question about an intuitive element in our
cognition, which is that we do intuit being in the data (data both of sense and
of consciousness). But this
intuiting is nothing but our understanding the data by grasping a meaning in
them, and then verifying this understanding through critical reflection that
leads to rational judgment. These
are two distinct acts that, together with the presentation of the data in
experience, make up the threefold structure of our cognition.
To demand, beyond this, a further act of intuiting being, is precisely
the intuitionist myth that Lonergan battles against without quarter.
I repeat: We intuit being because we are able to correctly understand the
data. Now, everyone can verify the
act of understanding, and everyone knows what it means to understand correctly,
because everyone has experience of these acts.
But I have yet to find anyone who could help me identify in my
intellectual experience the mysterious act of intuiting being that the
intuitionists speak of. Just this is Lonergan’s whole thesis. According
to Coreth, the task of philosophical reflection is to mediate transcendentally
the immediate knowledge of being that Gilson speaks of. I confess that, here and in several other passages, I find it
unclear what Coreth intends by the verb "mediate”, even when it is
qualified by “transcendentally”. Nor
do I get much help from my knowledge of Kant, to whom Coreth is evidently
alluding. As I understand it,
transcendental investigation is simply introspective investigation applied to
cognitional (and volitional) operations. These
have a transcendental import in the Scholastic sense, because they extend to all
of reality. Such an investigation
differs from a generic phenomenological investigation in that what it reaches is
the invariant intentionality structures of the human subject, and thus what is
ultimate and intrinsically normative in all intentional activity.
Now, this kind of investigation does not mediate an immediate intuition
of being. Rather, if conducted
rigorously, it reveals that there is no such intuition—unless one wishes to
use the word “intuition” to designate precisely the intellectual acts of the
cognitional structure that I mentioned above. In other
words, the basic opposition is not, as Coreth seems to suppose, between an
immediate and uncritical realism[61]
and a transcendentally mediated knowledge of being. One might try to mediate our knowledge transcendentally and
end up admitting an immediate intuition of being in the sense of naïve realism.
In that case, despite any transcendental mediation, one would still be in
the uncritical realism that Lonergan criticizes in Gilson.
This seems to be precisely Coreth’s position, as I stressed in my
previous essay and have confirmed in the present study.
A
position should be called naïve realism if: 1) it recognizes our capacity to
know the real, 2) but it bases this capacity on a simple act of intuiting being
which is conceived on the model of ocular vision and which, as ultimate, is not
further specifiable or reducible. 3) This naïve realism will be sensist or not,
according to whether the intuition that establishes the immediate relation of
cognition to the real is an intuition of sense or of intellect.
Thus, the naïve realism of Kant is sensist[62],
while that of Gilson and a number of other Neoscholastics is not. It is
easy to see that it is the second of these points that discriminates between
uncritical and critical realism. In
this connection, one should note Lonergan’s very illuminating discussion of
the “picture thinking” characteristic of uncritical realism, in his article
on cognitional structure[63].
Now, on this second point Kant and Gilson are in agreement.
Thus, Lonergan states that “Prof. Gilson is equally convinced that
perception is the one manner in which cognitional activity attains objectivity. He differs from Kant, not on the question of principle, but
on the question of fact”[64].
If I have correctly interpreted the “knowing of the performance” (Vollzugswissen)
in Coreth’s Metaphysik, and the “immediacy of spiritual insight (Einsicht)”[65]
in his present article, then one must say that Coreth also shares this
principle. The difference between
Coreth and Gilson is that what Gilson asserts in general, Coreth restricts to
the particular case of the reality that I am, in the act of questioning or in
some other intellectual activity. But
this restriction is what Lonergan calls the difference between the “already
out there now” and the “already in here now”.
It does not change the nature of the realism in question.
But
perhaps it would be fairer to speak of a basic ambiguity in Coreth’s
epistemology. For in many important
passages in the Metaphysik he rejects intuitionism and empiricism and
works out an acute critical theory of knowledge.
In his review, Lonergan pointed out and explicated this aspect of
Coreth’s thought. Nonetheless,
the ambiguity remains. Here and
there one meets with passages or lines of thought that move in the direction of
intuitionism. With his recent
stand, Coreth has reinforced this tendency toward intuitionism, instead of
resolving the basic ambiguity. But
I admit that, since my observations tend to emphasize the passages with an
intuitionistic bent, they may have the effect of neglecting or misrepresenting
the critically valid contribution made by the Metaphysik.
The present study should therefore be considered as complementing
Lonergan’s extremely illuminating and positive review in this Journal.
2. The
notion of being is not mediated. We saw
above that, according to Coreth, Lonergan’s view is that being is what is
mediated or to be mediated. I
believe that this way of presenting Lonergan’s position is incorrect. It is therefore appropriate to re-examine what Lonergan says
about the knowledge we have of being. Is being
mediated or not? First of all, I
reply that the question is, more exactly, about our knowledge of being.
Now, with regard to human knowledge of being, the fundamental distinction
is between (1) the notion of being, and (2) knowledge in the true and proper
sense, which is had in judgment: ens iudicio vero (i.e. rationali)
cognoscitur [being is known in true (i.e., rational) judgment][66].
The insistence with which Lonergan distinguishes between the
“concept” of being and every other concept, to the point of calling the
former a notion rather than a concept[67],
is meant to highlight the completely peculiar nature of this “concept”.
How do we obtain every other concept?
Through an act of insight into data.
Thus, each of these concepts is a posteriori.
How do we obtain the concept of being? Negatively,
“It cannot result from an insight into being, for such an insight would be an
understanding of everything about everything, and such understanding we have not
attained”[68].
Again: “If the notion of being expressed and resulted from an insight,
that insight would have to be an understanding not merely of the whole of the
actual universe but also of the total range of possible universes.
Such an understanding would be identical with Aquinas’ actus totius
entis [act of all being], that is, with God (Sum. theol., I, q.
79, a. 2 c). Since
man possesses a notion of being yet obviously fails to satisfy Aquinas’
concept of God, man’s notion cannot result from an act of understanding”[69].
And again, in a paper in which Lonergan relates Insight to Thomist
philosophy, he writes “You will agree, I believe, that there is one and only
one ens per essentiam [being through its own essence], that it is not an
immediate object of our knowledge in this life, that the only immediate objects
of our present knowledge are entia per participationem [beings by
participation]. It follows that our
intellectual knowledge of being cannot result from abstraction of essence.
For, if from a horse I abstract essence, what I abstract is the essence,
not of being, but of horse; if from a man I abstract essence, what I abstract is
the essence not of being, but of man; and the same holds for every other
immediate object of our present knowledge.
No being by participation can yield us knowledge of the essence of being,
because no being by participation has the essence of being”[70].
Positively,
Lonergan sees the origin of our intellectual knowledge of being in the
intelligent and rational dynamism of our consciousness operating at the
intellectual level. This
intellectual consciousness is identical with our pure desire to know, which is
an intelligent and rational awareness. In
other words, the realm of human consciousness as intelligent and rational is the
realm of intentionality. Thus, in
the three passages quoted above, after his negative delimitation of the notion
of being, Lonergan continues: “It is… the orientation of intelligent and
rational consciousness towards an unrestricted objective”[71].
“Accordingly, we were led to the discovery that the notion of being has
its origin and ground in an anticipative desire to understand, in a capacity to
inquire and reflect”[72].
“By such reasoning I was led in Insight to affirm that our
natural intellectual desire to know was a natural intellectual desire to know
being. The desire, precisely
because it is intelligent, is a notion. But
the notion is not any innate idea or concept or knowledge.
It is a desire for ideas, for concepts, for knowledge but, of itself, it
is merely discontented ignorance without ideas, without concepts, without
knowledge”[73].
“The spontaneously operative notion of being has to be placed in the
pure desire to know”[74].
Now, I
see no reason why an intellectual knowledge of being so characterized, which
underpins all cognitional contents, penetrates them all, and constitutes them as
cognitional[75], should be called a
mediated knowledge. It is so little
mediated that it excludes even that mediation that each of our concepts has, the
mediation of data. This is why I
have strongly underlined its a priori character.
It is our a priori in an absolute sense, the end point reached in
the search for the conditions of the possibility of human knowledge.
To use the words of Coreth, it is “that which we always have already
and which we perform in all our inquiring and knowing”[76].
It is just “the immediate”[77].
But this immediate is mediated, i.e., is implemented, in the threefold
structure so as to arrive at human knowledge in the true and proper sense. We have
already seen that this first, this a priori, is not “pure
objectivity”[78],
as Coreth takes it to be. To say
that the subject originally and ineluctably is a sense of being to itself
obviously is not to conceive being originally as an object. The sense of being is indeed at the root of the possibility
of all objectivization, but this does not mean that it is knowledge of any
object. It is prior to the
difference between subject and object known as being. We have likewise seen that this sense of being is not empty.
Consequently, its thematization in the heuristic notion of being[79]
is not at all tautological, but is the true transcendental definition of being,
a definition based on the operations by which we properly know proportionate
beings and analogically know transcendent being[80]. The
definition of being as nothing but the objective of our pure desire to know can
be accepted as correct, indeed, as the only definition possible for us, if one
has truly reached a rational conception of the real.
Otherwise, it will seem contentless and tautological[81],
so that one will resort to something else to fill it in.
Obviously, for Lonergan too the notion of being has to be filled in, for
it is a heuristic notion. It is
only by implementing the cognitional structure on which the second-order
definition of being is based that we gradually pass from anticipation to
effective knowledge. But it remains
that the notion of being is the obverse that determines what the reverse must be
like if it is to be being. What it
means to be intelligible and absolute, so as to be reality, is something that
only the a priori notion of being can tell us.
Hence, we must say that Lonergan intends his operative definition as
already determining the content of being, insofar as only those contents that
answer to our intelligent and reasonable anticipation of the intelligible and
absolute are being, and they are being to the extent that they answer to this
anticipation. In this sense, which
is the one that counts here, the a priori notion of being has a content
that is not and cannot be determined a posteriori.
Here we have the entire problem of arriving at a rational conception of
the real and remaining in it.
If one
does not accept that the real is completely intelligible, what will one resort
to in order to fill in the heuristic definition of being? To the solid sense of reality based on the sensible
integration of the data of sense[82].
One has not yet arrived at critical realism if one doubts that
understanding correctly is knowing[83],
or that “the impalpable act of rational assent is the necessary and sufficient
condition for knowledge of reality”[84].
In Coreth this empiricism no doubt is highly purified, so that in order
to have the sense of reality originally, it is enough to have the internal
experience of oneself as a questioning reality.
But even thus refined and spiritualized, the position remains an
empiricism that amounts to naïve realism.
Only one who, through a radical intellectual purification, has arrived at
what Lonergan calls intellectual conversion[85],
will be able to “be content” with the definition of being as that which is
known, not in solid internal or external experience, but in moving beyond
experience by understanding what experience has merely presented and by
affirming it rationally. With
this, we go on to examine the knowledge of being in the judgment. We wish to see whether there, at least, one can accept the
interpretation that for Lonergan, being is the mediated.
3. The
knowledge of being in the judgment is structured, but not necessarily mediated. I said
above that knowledge in the true and proper sense occurs only in the judgment.
Referring to the Metaphysik, Lonergan expresses Coreth’s
position this way: “For Prof. Gilson being or the concept of being is
‘seen’ in the data of sense. But
for Fr. Coreth being is what is asked about with respect to the data of sense.
So far from being seen in data, being, for Fr. Coreth, is what is
intended by going beyond the data. For
questioning goes beyond an already known to an unknown that is to be known: for
Fr. Coreth the already known is the datum, and the unknown to be known is
being”[86]. Coreth
expresses some perplexity about recognizing his position in this passage.
To him, Lonergan seems to be describing “an occurrence of mediation (Vermittlungsgeschehen)
that can come to no conclusion because it has no beginning”[87].
We saw in the last section that there is such a beginning: the
notion of being, which is precisely the primordial knowledge of being that makes
every question possible[88].
There is no reason to ask for more, unless one has failed to overcome
one’s yearning for a knowledge based on animal extroversion.
The immediacy of being that Coreth believes is missing in Lonergan’s
mediation[89]
is the immediacy of something that would be known as being before an intelligent
question and a critical question had been asked, and before they had been
answered. Obviously Lonergan would
not accept this kind of immediacy, even with regard to the knowledge of
ourselves as realities[90]. Let us
now see if the process described by Lonergan is truly a mediation.
Even though Coreth does not explicitly raise this question, I consider it
of capital importance for assessing in what sense being for Lonergan is
mediated. The distinction to be
made here is between structure and mediation.
In what sense can one say that being is mediated?
In the sense that all human knowledge of reality occurs through the
threefold structure of experiencing, understanding, and judging.
But this does not mean that all our knowledge of reality is mediated, if
by mediation one means something other than the structure—for example, an
inferential kind of process.
Direct
or immediate knowledge of reality and structured knowledge do not exclude each
other—except to naïve realists, for whom the meaning of immediacy is borrowed
from the intuition principle. Properly
speaking, it is knowledge as structure and knowledge as intuition that exclude
each other. Now, it is obvious that
mediated, or reflexive, or discursive knowledge ultimately presupposes
immediate, or direct, or intuitive knowledge.
But such immediate knowledge does not occur through an “immediate
intuition” of reality that would be something other than our capacity to grasp
a meaning in what is purely given at the experiential level, and to verify the de
facto absolute character of that meaning.
The recognition of direct knowledge must not lead to the rejection of the
structure principle in favor of the intuition principle.
Now, at the base of every type of intuitionist theory of knowledge lies
just such reasoning. It is
difficult for me not to recognize this intuitionist confusion when Coreth
writes: “The phenomenological element … [is] the immediacy … which must be
mediated”[91].
Immediacy of what? Of the knowledge of being?
But this knowledge never happens with the mere datum, which Coreth
described a little earlier as “something ‘given’ and ‘appearing’—a
phenomenon in the broadest sense”[92].
I certainly do not intend to support a mediation to infinity, without
anything immediate to be mediated. But
the required immediacy should not be sought in the datum or in sense, or in a
spiritual intuition conceived along the lines of sensible intuition.
The immediacy, or the contact with reality, or the bridge—choose
whatever image you please—that unites us with reality consists in our
intention of being. Naturally, this
involves an immediate relation to reality as intended, i.e., as sought. The same relation to reality, no longer only as intended but
as reached, is immediate in judgment, since judgment is the unconditioned
positing that answers to our intention of being. No
doubt, there is mediated knowledge of reality.
It is outside the scope of the present inquiry to examine how mediation
occurs in these instances. But in
general I would say that mediation occurs through a deductive process based on
the principle of causality. In
these cases, we have direct knowledge of some reality that mediates the
knowledge of another reality that does not enter into our experience.
This occurs in fact for many realities that belong to proportionate
being, and it occurs in principle for our knowledge of transcendent being.
But this mediated knowledge, too, occurs through the threefold structure
of experiencing, understanding, and judging.
In particular, at the level of understanding, mediated knowledge involves
the working of the principle of causality, a fundamental law of our spirit as
operative intelligible. Hence, it
is indeed true that mediated knowledge, in the sense of deductive knowledge,
ultimately presupposes immediate knowledge.
This is why Lonergan emphasizes concrete judgments of fact, which are our
entrance door to the real[93].
These are what others call immediate judgments of existence or judgments
of experience. But what is at issue is precisely judgment.
Now, a judgment is always the end point of a three-step process. There is
a more direct way only if one reduces the reality proportionate to human knowing
to one dimension. That is the way
imagined by the naïve realist, for whom the essence of knowing is manifested in
the activity of seeing. “Empiricism
as a method rests on an elementary confusion.
What is obvious in knowing is, indeed, looking.
Compared to looking, insight is obscure, and grasp of the unconditioned
is doubly obscure. But empiricism
amounts to the assumption that what is obvious in knowing is what knowing
obviously is. That assumption is
false, for if one would learn mathematics or science or philosophy or if one
sought common-sense advice, then one would go to a man that is intelligent and
reasonable rather than to a man that is stupid and silly”[94].
4.
Assessment of the distinction between intuitive and discursive knowing from the
critical point of
view.
(1)
Knowing is either ex parte subiecti [on the side of the subject] or ex
parte obiecti [on the side of the object].
The former is consciousness (experience of oneself).
It is constitutive of every psychological act, whether cognitive (knowing
ex parte obiecti) or appetitive. (2)
Knowing ex parte obiecti is either experiencing or understanding or
judging. Only in the judgment,
considered not as an act detached from the preceding ones, but as bringing to
completion the previous steps of experiencing and understanding, is there human
knowing in the true and proper sense, i.e., knowing of reality. (3)
Knowing ex parte obiecti can occur in either the direct or the
introspective mode, depending on whether the data (experience) to which the
further levels of understanding and judgment relate are data of sense or data of
consciousness[95]. It is
clear that intuition has no place in this division, if by intuition one means a
human knowing in the true and proper sense that is not triadically structured.
Hence, for Lonergan the distinction between intuitive and discursive
knowing is not relevant from a systematic point of view.
For what is intuitive knowing? Is
there an exercise of understanding in it or not?
Does this understanding deal, through an inquiry that can be more or less
articulated or spontaneous or undifferentiated, with something that has been
presented to us, or does it not? And
again, is this understanding—which substantially is the grasping of a meaning
in the data—necessarily true, or does it need to be verified?
If one answers yes to the second and third of these questions, and if (as
must happen if one truly introspects one’s own acts) one recognizes the
necessity of verifying whatever is understood, then one recognizes that no
intuitive (unstructured) mode of knowing reality exists that would be
essentially different from discursive (triadic) knowing. But it
is necessary to be quite clear about this central thesis of Insight.
It takes such a strong stand, in the face of 2000 years of philosophical
speculation from Plato to Kant, that it has aroused scandal or perplexity in not
a few readers of Insight. The
systematic division I have traced above is only a schema.
In particular, it speaks of understanding only to indicate the central
act of the structure. But it does
not follow that this exhausts all that can be said about understanding!
In fact, we are only at the beginning.
The modes in which our understanding operates are numerous.
They emerge as science progresses and consciousness becomes
differentiated. There are manifold
patterns of consciousness or of experience, according to which both our
cognitional process and our psychological life in general are concretely
configured[96].
Thus, there is room for the mode of knowing proper to common sense and
for that of science, for the intuitive understanding of the first and for the
analytic and discursive understanding of the second.
There is room for the intuition of the expert and for the inquiring and
learning of the lay person. There
is room for the flash of genius of an understanding that grasps at once a vast
field of implications, and there is room for progress in reasoning through the
gradual development of insight[97],
for the openness of all human understanding to further developments,
integrations, and corrections. There
is room for what is called knowledge by connaturality, for the role that
feelings and existential decisions play in our knowing in the moral and
religious fields. There is room for
the historical and social elements, whether of progress or of decline, that
constitute the concrete horizon within which man as “incarnate inquirer”[98]
operates. In
particular, there is room for the interpersonal knowledge that is one of the
most-heard themes in philosophical reflection today.
Lonergan did a broad analysis of scientific knowledge and dedicated two
precious chapters to common-sense knowledge, but he recognizes openly that the
treatment of interpersonal relations in Insight is skimpy[99].
But here too the precise question relevant to the epistemology of Insight
is: How does interpersonal knowledge occur? or, equivalently, What kind of
intelligence brings it about? No
doubt one will have to bring out the horizon of pre-comprehension within which
this type of knowing takes place, the role that feelings and existential
decisions play in it. But this does
not invalidate Lonergan’s thesis that intuitionism is excluded from every case
of true and proper human knowing. In
a further chapter on interpersonal knowledge, Lonergan would again put these
questions: Is the particular kind of understanding that determines interpersonal
knowledge based on data or not? Does
it require verification, in a way peculiar to it, or not?
If one answers yes to these questions—which I do not see can be
avoided—then interpersonal knowledge does not provide any objection to
Lonergan’s thesis about human knowing as a structure. Hence,
the underlying schema, within which all these differentiations are located and
interpreted, always remains the same: the schema of knowing as structure.
When one has recognized the thesis of human knowing as structure in all
its import, the myth of intuitionism falls, as well as the distinction between
intuitive and discursive knowing. To
repeat: When this distinction refers to something confirmed by introspective
analysis, it does not reach what is essential.
It does not eliminate what is essential to the thesis of knowing as
structure. On the other hand, when it pretends to be an essential
distinction, it is false.
Instead
of the distinction between intuitive and discursive knowing, Lonergan would
distinguish, at the limit, between the Aristotelian νόησις
νοήσεος [understanding of understanding][100]
and the structure of human knowing. But
how was the first member of this distinction obtained?
Through a very precise process of analogy that starts from a kind of
intuition that, far from being opposed to the structure, is actually its central
element. For human νόησις [understanding] is always an understanding of data:
“The faculty of understanding understands the forms in the images.”[101],
or again, “The soul never understands without an image”[102].
For just this reason, human νόησις
always needs verification, in a more or less articulated way, in the reflective
stage of cognitional process. To
speak of an intuitive knowing that is at once the negation and preservation (Aufhebung,
sublation) of cognitional structure is to expand to infinity this central act of
human knowing, so that it no longer needs either data or critical reflection.
The νόησις
νοήσεος is the intelligible that is identical with the
intelligence that knows it[103],
and it is therefore in an eminent manner true, and thus real.
In it, reality is identified, without any residue, with meaning. * *
* My
observations can end here. Perhaps
they are scattered observations, yet I imagine they have some importance for
working out a theory of knowledge that is truly critical. By this I mean, beyond names that change with philosophical
tastes, a theory that accords with the facts.
Now, the cognitional facts are facts of consciousness.
Lonergan proposes a criterion by which the affirmations of metaphysics
can be subjected to verification[104].
This criterion, to reduce every dispute to a question of concrete
psychological fact, is all the more valid for the theory of knowledge.
Certainly, the psychological facts on which I base my alternative to some
defining points in Coreth’s epistemology are not all the facts that would be
relevant for a more complete and concrete theory of knowledge.
Many of the questions debated in epistemology today are precisely at this
more concrete level. One thinks of
linguistic analysis, hermeneutics, or the sociology of knowledge. But
assurance about the value of a general theory of knowledge can never be
dismissed as passé. This means
that today the eternal question still imposes itself: What is being? How do we know being? Coreth
rightly stresses from the beginning of his paper that the decisive difference
between him and Lonergan lies in their respective understanding of being.
Perhaps, I would like to add at the end of my study, this difference is
greater than it might seem on first reading the Metaphysik. The method these pages would like to propose is that, in
order to answer the question of being, more attention needs to be paid to the
subject than it usually receives.
[Translation
by Donald E. Buzzelli]
* [Originally published as Immediatezza e mediazione della conoscenza dell’essere: Riflessioni sull’epistemologia di E. Coreth e B. Lonergan, in Gregorianum 53 (1972) pp. 45-87.] # [Present address: Hochschule für Philosophie, Kaulbachstr. 31a, 80539 München, Germany.] [1] E. Coreth, S.J., Metaphysik, Eine methodisch-systematische Grundlegung, Innsbruck-Wien-München 1961. In 1964 a slightly revised second edition appeared. Citations in the present study are to the latter edition. [An abridged English edition has appeared as Emerich Coreth, Metaphysics, ed. Joseph Donceel, S.J. (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968). Geist im Welt has been translated as Karl Rahner, Spirit in the World, tr. William Dych, S.J. (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968).] [2] Lonergan, Metaphysics as Horizon, in Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan: Volume 4, Collection, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (University of Toronto Press, 1988), pp. 188-204. [Originally published in Gregorianum 44 (1963), 307-318.] [3] Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan: Volume 3, Insight: A Study of Human Understanding, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (University of Toronto Press, 1992). Citations will be to the original pagination, with the Toronto edition pagination in brackets. [4] G.B. Sala, S.J., Seinserfahrung und Seinshorizont nach E. Coreth und B. Lonergan, in Zeitschrift für katholische Theologie 89 (1967) 294-338. [5] E. Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being: An Attempt to Answer Bernard Lonergan, in Language, Truth, and Meaning: Papers from the International Lonergan Congress, 1970, ed. Philip McShane (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1972), pp. 33-48 and 317-319. [Previously published as E. Coreth, S.J., Unmittelbarkeit und Vermittlung des Seins. Versuch einer Antwort an Bernard J.F. Lonergan, S.J., in Zeitschrift für katholische Theologie 92 (1970) 313-327.] On the Congress, see J. Navone, Ongoing Collaboration: The First International Lonergan Congress, in Gregorianum 51 (1970) 541-560. [6] I quote here some of the most significant statements Lonergan makes on these pages: “How does the knower get beyond himself to a known? The question is, we suggest, misleading. It supposes the knower to know himself and asks how he can know anything else… We contend that, while the knower may experience himself or think about himself without judging, still he cannot know himself until he makes the correct affirmation, I am… Hence, we place transcendence, not in going beyond a known knower, but in heading for being within which there are positive differences and, among such differences, the difference between object and subject.” (Insight, 377 [401f]) Again, concerning the absolute objectivity that “pertains to single judgments as single” (ibid. 378 [402]) he writes “the absolute aspect of objectivity does not imply any subject-object relation; it constitutes the entry of our knowing into the realm of being…” (ibid. [403]) [7] With regard to Coreth’s assertion that Lonergan understands being as objectivity (Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 39), I would like to point out that for Lonergan everything that is known as being is known in a judgment. Now, what is known in a judgment is known ad modum obiecti [as an object]. But this is just another way of saying that Lonergan does not recognize an experience of oneself (knowledge ex parte subiecti [on the side of the subject]), an awareness of the subject as subject, as providing knowledge of being. This is precisely his rejection of intuitionism, even under the form of the “already in here now” (Cf. Insight, 499 [523]). [8] Sala, Seinserfahrung und Seinshorizont, 328-332. [9] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 39. On this same page Coreth expresses Lonergan’s thought with the thesis: “Object is that which can be asserted in true judgments”. It would be more in accord with Lonergan’s position to say “being” instead of “object”, since his fundamental thesis is that “ens iudicio vero cognoscitur [being is known by true judgment]”. As a matter of fact, the scope of the two theses is the same since, as pointed out in note 7, the being that we know in the judgment is always known ad modum obiecti. [10] Ibid., 40. [11] Lonergan clearly had already reached the position of Insight in his earlier study of knowledge in St. Thomas. “The critical problem… is not a problem of moving from within outwards, of moving from a subject to an object outside the subject. It is a problem of moving from above downwards, of moving from an infinite potentiality commensurate with the universe towards a rational apprehension that seizes the difference of subject and object in essentially the same way that it seizes any other real distinction. Thus realism is immediate, not because it is naïve and unreasoned and blindly affirmed, but because we know the real before we know such a difference within the real as the difference between subject and object” (Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan: Volume 2, Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (University of Toronto Press, 1997), pp. 98f.]. But it seems that there is a nearly insuperable confusion in the minds of many between immediate realism (we know being immediately) and knowledge by intuition (in the sense of denying the cognitional structure)! Hence one must note that Lonergan explicitly maintains an immediate realism, but does not thereby resort to the immediate intuition of being that characterizes intuitionism or perceptionism. [12] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 41. [13] Ibid., 42. [14] Ibid. [15] If the problem of knowledge must be posed in terms of the knowledge of being, Coreth obviously is not criticizing Lonergan when he writes: “’Being’ means not only the being of objects, nor only the realm of possible objectivity. It also means the being which we ourselves are, i.e., which we ourselves realise and experience as the being that sets everything that simply is or happens into its actuality” (ibid., 41). [16] Ibid., 42. [17] Cf. Insight, 499 [523]. Sala, Seinserfahrung und Seinshorizont, 327, note 60. [18] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 39. [19] Lonergan, Metaphysics as Horizon, in Collection, 204. [20] “Since according to Lonergan the concept of the existent means the ‘objective of the pure cognitional striving’ [Cf. ‘Being… is the objective of the pure desire to know’, Insight, 348 [372]—Fr. Sala’s parenthesis], then being means pure objectivity” (Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 44). But Lonergan, with his heuristic definition of being, is not at all denying that the intentional dynamism, and therefore the sense of what it anticipates, originates in the subject. Indeed, it is that very subject, since spirit is the being that is present to itself. I attempt to bring out this radical “subjectivity” of being when I treat the notion of being, especially when I illustrate the a priori character of this notion. To say that being is the objective of the pure desire to know is not to conceive being as what is in front (ob-iectum, Gegen-stand) of a subject that is outside or ignorant of being. It is, rather, to conceive man as radically a seeker of being, and also—or, rather, first of all—of that being that he is himself. We shall see later that the heuristic definition of being is the only one possible for us as humans who do not enjoy an insight, in the full sense, into being, and that this definition implies a rational conception of the real. [21] Lonergan, Metaphysics as Horizon, in Collection, 191. [22] Ibid., 192. [23] Insight, 397 [422]. [24] Ibid., 748 [769]. [25] It should be noted, however, that Chap. XI discusses consciousness within the broader perspective of the affirmation of oneself as a knower, which is the knowledge of oneself as being, i.e., as an object. [26] I have presented the fundamental elements of Lonergan’s treatment of consciousness in Seinserfahrung und Seinshorizont, esp. in 300-305 and 332-337, and previously in L’analisi della coscienza umana in B. Lonergan, in La Scuola Cattolica, 92 (1964) 517-536. [27] Lonergan, Cognitional Structure, in Collected Works of Bernard Lonergan: Volume 4, Collection, ed. Frederick E. Crowe and Robert M. Doran (University of Toronto Press, 1988), pp. 210f. [28] Insight, 360 [384]. [29] Ibid., 642 [665]. [30] Sala, Seinserfahrung und Seinshorizont, 314. [31] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 42. [32] Ibid. [33] This is seen more fully in Sala, Seinserfahrung und Seinshorizont, 332-337. [34] Coreth certainly recognizes the conscious character of cognitive acts, but he does not systematically interpret consciousness as experience. I think this is because for Coreth, structure is not the key notion in his theory of knowledge. In fact, while he does a broad analysis of the phenomenon of the question in the Metaphysik, he gives neither fundamental value nor systematic significance to the distinction between questions at the second level of the structure and questions at the third level. [35] Ibid., 328. [36] Coreth, Metaphysik, 136. [37] Ibid., 137. [38] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 41. [39] Ibid., 42. But here the expression would suggest that the horizon of being has some precedence with respect to the experience of oneself as an existent. Thus, the “thereby” of the Metaphysik (“von dem her” 136; “daraus” 137) would not apply here. [40] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 45. [41] E. Gilson, Réalisme thomiste et critique de la connaissance, Paris 1939, 215, 225f. [42] Coreth, Metaphysik, 137. [43] Ibid. [44] Ibid., 136. [45] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 42. [46] Ibid., 41. [47] But this is not at all a matter of deduction. The knowing in question is identical to the experience of our intentionality. [48] Obviously, not the question as formulated, or as differentiated according to the historical, social, and personal elements by which our intentionality is implemented. [49] I consider here only the a priori at the intellectual level. In what sense one should speak of an a priori at the empirical level does not concern us directly. [50] Plato, Meno, 80d. [“And how will you enquire, Socrates, into that which you do not know? What will you put forth as the subject of enquiry? And if you find what you want, how will you ever know that this is the thing which you did not know?”—Jowett translation.] [51] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 41f. [52] Insight, 322f [346f]. [53] Ibid., 499 [523]. [54] It is this conception of the real as having only one dimension, the dimension of sense, that Lonergan expresses with his ever-recurring formula “already out there now”. [55] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 34. [56] Ibid. 43. [57] Ibid. [58] I. Kant, Kritik der Reinen Vernunft [Critique of Pure Reason], A 19 = B 33. [“In whatever manner and by whatever means a mode of knowledge may relate to objects, intuition is that through which it is in immediate relation to them, and to which all thought as a means is directed.”—Norman Kemp Smith translation.] [59] M. Heidegger, Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik, Frankfurt a.M. 1965, 29. [Martin Heidegger, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, tr. James S. Churchill (Indiana Univ. Press, 1962 and 1968), p. 28.] [60] Lonergan, Cognitional Structure, in Collection, 215. [61] Such a realism claims that what establishes an intentional connection with being, and enables us finally to reach being, is some sort of intuition of being. This intuition is not identified with the performance of the intentio intendens [intending intention] in understanding and judgment. [62] Cf. Kant, Kritik der Reinen Vernunft, A 19 = B 33; note the ever-recurring affirmation: “Every intuition of ours is sensible” in A 252, B 146, 151, 165, 302 note, etc. But Kant recognizes activities superior to sense and admits the thing in itself as a true reality. Hence his naïve realism becomes, with these correctives, a realism of reality-for-us, and thus a phenomenalism. [63] Lonergan, Cognitional Structure, in Collection, 214-219. [64] Lonergan, Metaphysics as Horizon, in Collection, 194. [65] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 43. [66] Sala, Seinserfahrung und Seinshorizont. On pp. 300-302 I discuss human knowledge in the true and proper sense, which is had in the implementation of the threefold structure. On pp. 312-316 I discuss the notion of being. See especially note 31. [67] Insight, 520f, 360, 369, and also 642 [544, 384, 393, 665]. [68] Ibid. 360 [384]. [69] Ibid. 521 [544]. [70] Lonergan, Insight, Preface to a Discussion, in Collection, 145f. [71] Insight, 360 [384]. [72] Ibid., 521 [544]. [73] Lonergan, Insight, Preface to a Discussion, in Collection, 147. [74] Insight, 353 ]377]. [75] Ibid. 356 [380]. [76] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 45. [77] Ibid. [78] Ibid., 44. [79] “Being [is] whatever is to be grasped intelligibly and affirmed reasonably” (Insight, 642 [665]). “Being is whatever is to be known by intelligent grasp and reasonable affirmation” (ibid., 391 [416]). [80] This definition can justly be called an operative definition, as Coreth does quoting Otto Muck. Lonergan calls it a definition “of the second order” (Ibid., 350 [374]) or “at a second remove” (ibid., 360f [384f]). But I take exception to the clarification that Muck tries to bring to it, when he interprets this second order as the order of reflection (O. Muck, Die transzendentale Methode in der scholastischen Philosophie der Gegenwart, Innsbruck 1964, 252. [Otto Muck, The Transcendental Method, tr. William D. Seidensticker (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968), pp. 277, 315.]) Lonergan definitely does not connect his “second order” with reflection. For him, reflection is the third constitutive moment in cognitional structure, the one that carries the process from thinking to judgment. In reflection one seeks the virtually unconditioned, on the basis of which one will posit absolutely, in the judgment, the synthesis that was merely thought in the concept. On the other hand, definitions of the second order, for Lonergan, also include the definitions of the metaphysical elements potency, form, and act (Insight, 432 [457]), because these definitions, like the definition of being, are based on the dynamic structure of cognitional process (ibid., 502 [526]). He clearly distinguishes an ordinary definition or definition of the first order, e.g., the definition of hydrogen, from the second-order definition of form. The definition of form in the metaphysical sense “does not refer immediately to reality… its immediate reference is to a type of cognitional activity and only through the occurrence, which is usually hypothetical, of such activity does it refer to being” (ibid., 503 [527]). [81] This seems to be Coreth’s opinion when he writes: “But if so functional a definition is not continually defined in terms of content—again, out of the performance of the cognition itself—then it remains a tautology”. (Coreth, Immediacy and the mediation of being, 44). The thesis that the real is the intelligible, the objective of our intelligent and rational operations, is anything but a tautology. It represents an achievement of capital importance in the history of western thought. With it, one recognizes that “reason is the criterion [of reality—Fr. Sala’s parenthesis] and, as well, it is reason—not the sense of reality—that gives meaning to the term ‘real’” (Lonergan, Verbum. Word and Idea in Aquinas, 20). Now, “The conflict between objectivity as extroversion and intelligence as knowledge has provided a fundamental theme in the unfolding of modern philosophy” (Insight, 413 [438]). Lonergan had previously described this same conflict as “the secular contrast between the solid sense of reality and the bloodless categories of the mind” (Lonergan, Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas, 20). [82] Ibid. See also Insight, 411-416 [437-441]. [83] Insight, xxviii [22]. [84] Ibid., 538 [561]. [85] Lonergan, De Deo Trino. II. Pars systematica. Romae 1964, 32. De Constitutione Christi ontologica et psychologica, Romae 1958, 15. Insight: Preface to a Discussion, in Collection, 148, note 10. Cognitional Structure, ibid., 218f. [86] Lonergan, Metaphysics as Horizon, in Collection, 200. Emphasis mine. [87] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 45. [88] In view of how fully Lonergan discusses this original anticipatory knowledge of being, I cannot see on what passages of Lonergan’s work Coreth bases his statement that “For Lonergan being is only the final, not also the first; it is only the goal of the mediation, not also its beginning, and hence not also that which in it—in dynamic identity—mediates itself and continues to define itself” (ibid., 46). With regard to the second of the difficulties Coreth advances here, see the clear response in Insight, 356f [380f] (an all-pervasive notion). [89] Coreth, Immediacy and the Mediation of Being, 46. [90] Cf. ibid., 45, toward the end. [91] Ibid., 37. [92] Ibid. [93] Cf. Insight, 340 [364]. [94] Ibid., 416 [441]. [95] Ibid., 272, 274 [298, 299f]. [96] For an illustrative, but not exhaustive, exposition see ibid., 181ff [204ff]. [97] With regard to intelligence as a synthetic and discursive capacity, see the very illuminating pages in Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas, 61-71. [98] Lonergan, Metaphysics as Horizon, in Collection, 204. [99] Insight, 731 [754] note. [100] Aristotle, Metaphysics, L XII, 9: 1074b 34. [Fr. Sala’s translation.] [101] Aristotle, De anima [On the soul], III, 7, 431b 2. [102] Ibid., 431a 16f. [103] “Since, then, understanding and the object of understanding are not different in the case of things that have not matter, the divine understanding and its object will be the same.” (Aristotle, Metaphysics, L XII, 9: 1075a 3-5 [McKeon edition as corrected by Fr. Sala]. See also Aristotle, De anima, III, 4: 430a 3f. [“Mind is itself understandable in exactly the same way as its objects are.”] [104] Insight, xi, 423 [5, 448]. |
|
|