The Metaphor of the Judge in the "Critique of Pure Reason" (B
xiii f): A Key for Interpreting the Kantian Theory of Knowledge†
by
Giovanni B. Sala SJ
Munich,
Hochschule für Philosophie
1.
The Metaphor of the Judge in the Preface to the
Second Edition
In
the Preface to the Second Edition of the "Critique of Pure Reason"
Kant speaks of this work as adopting a radically new method of thought (B xviii).
Only such a transformation, he says, is able to achieve that "reform of
metaphysics" for the sake of which Lambert, as far back as 1765, had
invited him to pool their efforts 1.
But in the Preface to the First Edition his speculations had already been
concentrated on this reform of metaphysics, for the sake of which human reason
found itself constrained "to undertake anew the most difficult of all its
tasks, namely, that of self-knowledge" (A xi).
In these comments from
April 1787, Kant sees his reform of metaphysics as an instance — no doubt the
most important one — of a conclusion he had reached in his pursuit of
self-knowledge, i.e., "that we can know a
priori of things only what we ourselves put
into them" (B xviii). He himself popularized his insight by comparing
it to the primary hypothesis of Copernicus (B xvi). The "Copernican
turn" thereby became the slogan for this "new method of thought"
(B xviii), which in reality was a "revolution" (B xi, xii, and xiii).
"Hitherto
it has been assumed that all our knowledge must conform to objects. But all
attempts to extend our knowledge of objects by establishing something in regard
to them a priori, by means of concepts, have, on this assumption, ended in
failure. We must therefore make trial whether we may not have more success in
the tasks of metaphysics, if we suppose that objects must conform to our
knowledge. This would agree better with what is desired, namely, that it should
be possible to have knowledge of objects a
priori, determining something in regard to them prior to their being
given" (B xvi).
This
"changed point of view" (B xvi) had already been achieved in
mathematics by the ancient Greeks and recently had occurred in natural science
also. Its thematization is the core of the new metaphysics that Kant proposes to
develop.
The metaphor of the judge
that I intend to study in this paper is found in this context. From the history
of modern natural science Kant cites three cases as examples of the new method.
This method is described in the following way with regard to its epistemological
significance:
"A
light broke upon all students of nature. They learned that reason has insight
only into that which it produces after a plan ["Entwurf: blueprint,
project] of its own, and that it must not allow itself to be kept, as it were,
in nature's leading-strings, but must itself show the way with principles of
judgment based upon fixed laws, constraining
nature to give answer to questions of reason's own determining. Accidental
observations, made in obedience to no previously thought-out plan, can never be
made to yield a necessary law, which alone reason is concerned to discover.
Reason, holding in one hand its principles, according to which alone concordant
appearances can be admitted as equivalent to laws, and in the other hand the
experiment which it has devised in conformity with these principles, must
approach nature in order to be taught by it.
It must not, however, do so in the character of a pupil who listens to
everything that the teacher chooses to say, but of
an appointed judge who compels the witnesses to
answer questions which he has himself formulated. Even physics, therefore,
owes the beneficent revolution in its point of view entirely to the happy
thought, that while reason must seek in
nature, not fictitiously ascribe to it, whatever as not being knowable through
reason's own resources has to be learnt, if
learnt at all, only from nature, it must adopt as its guide, in so seeking, that
which it has itself put into nature" (B
xiii f).
This
text is usually understood as an anticipation of the "changed point of
view" in metaphysics that follows soon after (B xvi), i.e., as another way
of saying that objects must conform to our knowledge. Under this interpretation
the text about metaphysics (B xvi) would be nothing but a generalization of the
text about natural science (B xiii f). This latter text, in which the comparison
with the judge appears, would therefore be adequately expressed by saying that
our understanding is itself the "lawgiver" of nature (A 126), or again
by saying that the understanding is itself "the author of the
experience" (B 127). There is no doubt that Kant understood the passage B
xiii f in that sense, since he connects what he says about the judge with what
has happened in physics: "even physics."
The purpose of the present
study is to show that the passage B xiii f, and in particular the comparison
with the judge, should nonetheless be understood in a more differentiated way
than it is in these simplified formulae. By analyzing the metaphor of the judge
we will clarify the core of the transcendental philosophy. Kant identifies this
core as the legislative function of the
understanding with respect to nature. But in my opinion this metaphor,
together with the idea of a legislative activity, also contains another idea,
that of verification through critical
reflection. Therefore both ideas must be held together, if one wishes to keep
transcendental reflection from ending up in a transcendental idealism that makes
man a kind of creator of the world and, just for that reason, does not do
justice to human knowledge as it in fact is. The exegetical reflections that
follow will lead us to discuss the issue itself, i.e., to the role that the
subject plays in objectively valid knowledge 2.
In other words, a different and better grounded interpretation of the judge's
questioning leads to a different understanding of the procedures of natural
science, and of human knowledge in general.
2.
Kant's Interpretation of the Procedures of Experimental Science and the
Comparison with the Judge's Interrogation
In
our principal text (B xiii f) two series of assertions must be distinguished.
Kant does not make this distinction clearly, which is why his application of the
metaphor to science does not do justice to the actual procedures of science.
1) "Reason has insight
only into that which it produces [hervorbringt]
after a plan of its own." The revolutionary character of modern physics
consists in its seeking in nature that which reason "has itself put
into [hineingelegt] nature." A
little farther on in B xviii we read: "We can know a
priori of things only what we ourselves put
into them" 3. All these
expressions move in the direction of a thetic (idealist) conception of
knowledge. Still, one cannot help seeing a certain tension in them, since Kant
speaks not only of a producing and a putting into, but also of a seeking and a
learning.
How are this seeking and
learning supposed to occur? They must occur in accordance with, i.e., under the
guidance of, what reason puts into nature. But with this, the "putting
into" acquires a meaning different from the passages where Kant speaks in
an undifferentiated way of the understanding as "lawgiver" (A 126), or
of our mind as originally introducing order and regularity into nature (A 125),
or of a "putting" concepts into experience (A 196), or of an "as
it were (!) prescribing [of] laws to nature" (B 159;
"Prolegomena" IV 320), or of a "previous a priori putting
into" according to the nature of our understanding ("Über eine neue
Entdeckung", VIII 216). Such a "putting into" or
"prescribing" for the purpose of seeking (which Kant expressly
distinguishes from a "fictitiously ascribing") can have only a hypothetical
significance. It is like a "plan," as Kant puts it, with which the
scientist approaches nature, but it cannot be a real prescribing of laws a
priori (B 163). It is not yet determined whether what reason anticipates
with its plan or its question really is in nature.
Kant saw that scientific
procedures include both a moment of projection, anticipation, and creativity in
which the subject has the initiative, and also a moment of verification in which
the object has the initiative, but he did not succeed in grasping exactly how
these two moments are related. Consequently he tends again and again to
formulate the first moment in a way that makes the second, seeking to learn,
impossible.
2) The second series of
assertions emphasizes the moment of planning as being, at first, only planning
[projecting]. Hence it is clearly distinguished from the subsequent moment of
verification, which aims at arriving at a knowledge of how things truly are.
Reason, holding in one hand the principles of its judgments according to
constant laws, must go ahead and compel nature to answer its questions.
The moment of planning takes place in the form of questions.
Reason, holding in the
other hand the experiment, which it has devised in conformity with these principles,
must approach nature in order to be taught
by it. Only because of the principles of reason can the appearances (or, better,
the data) be put into that connection that constitutes a determinate law. In
other words, reason grasps as an explanation of the data only what it itself
with its plan [projection] has (hypothetically!) anticipated; it finds only what
it asks about. The experiment then plays the role of an arbiter with respect to
the planning and creative moment. Through the experiment the scientist seeks to
know whether his plan is only his own idea, however brilliant, or whether it
corresponds to reality.
It remains to clarify what
exactly those "principles" are with which reason must go ahead in its
effort to arrive at knowledge of nature. An answer to this question would refer,
in Kant's sense, to the categories of the pure understanding in the first part
of the Analytic in the "Critique of Pure Reason", to the synthetic
principles of the pure understanding in the second part, and also to the
transcendental ideas in the Dialectic with their regulative use. Furthermore,
Kant is thinking of a system of principles, like those he developed in the
"Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science" of 1786. According to a
study by P. Plaass, the "Metaphysical Foundations" provide "a
system of principles that indicate how what is sought is manifested in
appearances, i.e., in motions." They represent "the canon, deduced a
priori with necessity, of that which reason must put into nature and in
conformity with which it must interrogate nature." 4
In our text Kant uses an
analogy to illustrate the way reason with its principles approaches nature in
order to learn from it. This analogy proves to be very useful for grasping how
the two moments (the creative moment of planning and the critical moment of
verifying) are related to each other. It is taken from the law, something that
Kant likes to do. Reason, with its principles (its intelligent plan) in one
hand, and with the experiment in the other, approaches nature "in order to
be taught by it." How is this learning supposed to take place? It is
not, says Kant, the learning of a pupil "who listens to everything that the
teacher chooses to say." 5
The scientist's learning, rather, takes place in the manner "of an
appointed judge who compels the witnesses to answer questions which he has
himself formulated."
If we now apply the
procedures of natural sciences to the judge, who operates in the context of the
law (which belongs to the human sciences), the procedures take the following
form. The judge is in search of a definite fact in accordance with a code of
civil or penal law. The witnesses know better than he what happened.
Nevertheless, the law entrusts the decision about what happened not to the
witnesses, but to the judge. The witnesses, as persons of common sense, know the
event in its existential aspect, as a part of daily life, like a fraud in
business, a traffic accident, a family tragedy, etc. But this does not directly
interest the judge in his capacity as a judge. What he wants to know is the
event as a fact that falls under the code of civil or penal law; he wants to
attain knowledge of a juridical reality, about which he will then have to pass
sentence according to the code of law.
In order to arrive at
knowledge of this reality, the judge asks specific questions, questions that are
relevant from the point of view of the law. He certainly learns about the case
from the witnesses, since he was not present at the event himself, but he would
not obtain the knowledge that interests him if he did not have a plan of it, an
anticipatory hypothesis. He knows the elements that make up a juridical fact,
and therefore he asks corresponding questions. The judge does
not impose anything onto reality; rather, he imposes onto the data that are
provided to him a certain interpretation as a possible
explanation of those data. He wants to know the reality as it is. But precisely
in order to know it objectively he has to take the initiative. He can do this
because he, and not the witnesses, possesses the science that makes it possible
for the legal reality to reveal itself. This possession amounts to an a
priori with respect to the fact that is to be known.
Only by virtue of questions
can the simple data provided by the witnesses become understood
data. They thus become a definite legal fact that, possibly, is the juridical
reality of the event. Starting with this intelligibility that interprets the
event, and evaluating all its elements, as well as clues and circumstances, the
judge reaches a certainty that is sufficient for him to issue his sentence
rationally and responsibly. This weighing of all the elements available to the
judge constitutes the moment of verification of what previously was only an
explanatory hypothesis. Here we have the counterpart of the experiment in
natural science, which has the purpose of deciding about the truth of a previous
explanatory hypothesis, and thus about the actual existence of the understood
reality which is meant.
3. The
Question and the Pre-Knowledge That Makes It Possible
In
the example of the judge, the key element is the question. On the basis of his
legal knowledge, the judge asks questions that are intended to enable him to
grasp a legally defined fact. Similarly, the scientist in his investigation of
nature formulates hypotheses as a possible
explanation of a natural phenomenon, forcing nature to answer his questions. The
defining characteristic of a scientific explanation is that in it things are
considered in their mutual relations (and not in relation to the subject!), and
that these relations are grasped in their quantitative aspects and expressed
mathematically. Something analogous can be said of the historian in his
researches into the past, of the man of common sense, etc. In all these cases
the person approaches reality with a specific knowledge, with a pre-knowledge
that makes it possible to ask questions about a reality and to know it under a
specific aspect.
The study of hermeneutics
has brought to light this condition for knowledge as it is found in the human
sciences, and has called it" Vorverständnis"
(preconception). Here, in the context of the metaphor of the judge, I would like
to call attention to two things. First, the need for a Vorverständnis — and
thus for a (relative) a priori — in order
to be able to know something at all, is not limited to the human sciences.
Second, rather than a Vorverständnis one
should speak of a pre-knowledge, since this condition of the possibility of
knowledge ultimately aims not only at understanding (Verstehen) things, but at
knowing them. It is true that this pre-knowledge first of all grounds a question
for intelligence ("what is this?"), but the same pre-knowledge plays a
no less decisive role in the subsequent moment, which is introduced by a
question for reflection: "is it so?" This leads to the judgment, in
which the object, that at first was only thought, is known in its status as a
reality 6.
There are various kinds of
pre-knowledge, which lead to various kinds of questions. But since they all have
been acquired, they all are a posteriori.
They are a priori only in relation to the knowledge we are seeking at the
moment. The judge acquired his legal knowledge at the university and in his
professional practice. Similar forms of learning are the basis of the
pre-knowledge of the scientist, the historian, the man of common sense. The
mentality of the man of common sense varies according to the time and place in
which he lives and is brought up. This pre-knowledge is a knowledge of a
determinate content, of specific objects, since it consists of all one knows
about objects of the natural world and of the human world.
This determinate
pre-knowledge is acquired by asking questions, but questions ultimately are
grounded in another pre-knowledge that is purely and entirely a
priori. Such a knowledge is subjective (rather than objective), in the sense
that it consists in the awareness that a person has of his own intelligence and
rationality. And it is operative in that from it proceed all questions and the
whole process of passing from questions to answers. Such a pure pre-knowledge
was not acquired, nor could it be acquired, by the subject. Rather, it is the
very intelligence and rationality of his spirit. It is the cognitive (and
volitional) dynamism with which every person is endowed, a dynamism that has an
unlimited range and, just for that reason, tends toward a knowledge of
everything, i.e., of being. As an intelligent and rational dynamism (or
intentionality, in philosophical terminology), it is capable of passing from not
knowing to knowing by asking questions solicited by the data of experience:
first a question for intelligence, and then a question for reflection. It is
only with the answer to this latter question that we succeed in knowing as a
reality that which we at first knew only as something given and then, as the
result of an act of understanding, as something thought
4.
The Metaphor of the Judge in the Context of Kant's Epistemological and
Metaphysica Position
The
metaphor of the judge who questions witnesses in order to arrive at knowledge of
a legal reality is found in the Preface to the Second Edition of the
"Critique of Pure Reason. A pre-face (Vor-rede) is, in reality, a post-face
(Nach-rede), i.e., a view of the whole of a work that is now concluded, in which
the author tries to highlight the basic idea in what he has written. In the case
of Kant's First Critique, this idea is a reform of the theory of knowledge and
the corresponding theory of being (metaphysics), to be worked out on the model
of modern natural science, whose validity was evident to Kant because of its
successes. The metaphor of the judge is intended to illustrate the
characteristic procedure of natural science: The scientist succeeds in knowing
(and dominating!) nature by asking it questions. The basic terms of the analogy
are, on the one hand, the principles proper to reason that give rise to
questions and, on the other hand, the experiment.
Modern science is distinguished from ancient science in the Aristotelian
tradition precisely by its constant appeal to experience. The problem lies in
knowing how these two moments of question and experiment are related to each
other. I have already pointed out a tension present in the text of B xiii f,
particularly where it says that reason puts into
nature that which it must seek in nature and so must learn
from it. I now propose to examine the "Critique of Pure Reason" in
order to see how Kant actually worked out his epistemology and metaphysics by
following the model of the procedures proper to natural science 7.
According to the important
text at the beginning of the "Transcendental Logic," A 50-52, properly
human knowledge consists in a binary structure of intuition and concept, where
intuition is understood as sense intuition, the only kind with which, according
to Kant, man is endowed. The Transcendental Aesthetic is dedicated to the first
component of this structure, and the Transcendental Analytic is concerned with
the second. With regard to the function performed by sense intuition, let it
suffice here to refer to the first two paragraphs of the Aesthetic, A 19 f. This
text is extremely important because here Kant clearly formulates not only the
role of intuition, but also the role of the concept, and thus presents the core
of his theory of knowledge. Sensible intuition is the only cognitive act that is
able to throw a bridge from the knowing subject to the reality to be known. But
this intuition has its own conditions, the forms of space and time.
Consequently, the object is not known as it is in itself, but as it appears to
the subject because of these a priori forms.
The text also speaks of
thought ("Denken"), i.e., of the acts of the understanding (Verstand),
saying that Denken is related directly to intuition, and therefore is related
only mediately to the object. Denken brings the content of the sensible
intuition to the concept, and thereby enables us to have properly human
knowledge (cf. A 50-52). But it is not able to go beyond the ontological status
of appearance that characterizes the object of intuition. On the contrary, the
application of the pure concepts 8
to the content of sensible experience confirms and, so to speak, reinforces the
character of what is thus known as being only an appearance. It is precisely the
a priori character of concepts that was at the origin of the "Konformitätsproblem"
or "antithetisches Problem" 9
that Kant formulated on February 21, 1772 when writing to Marcus Herz, and from
which the "Critique of Pure Reason" resulted after years of
reflection.
The Transcendental Analytic
deals with the function that the understanding with its a
priori concepts (categories) has in the constitution of human knowledge. The
text that is directly dedicated to this problem is the "Transcendental
Deduction of the Pure Concepts of Understanding." Now, in the letter to
Herz, Kant had posed the question of the conformity of our a
priori concepts to the object from a realist point of view. He had asked how
these concepts can conform to a reality (and thus enable us to know it) if that
reality does not depend on our knowing it. But in the "Critique of Pure
Reason" he answers by eliminating the realist premise from which the
problem arose.
The outcome of the
Transcendental Deduction therefore is that "objects known a priori are not
objects in themselves, but appearances; they are not independent of us but are
regulated by our understanding, which acts as the 'author of the experience' (B
127)." 10
Indeed, Kant writes at the end of the Transcendental Deduction:
"If
the objects with which our knowledge has to deal were things in themselves, we
could have no a priori concepts of them ...
But if, on the other hand, we have to deal only with appearances, it is not
merely possible, but necessary, that certain a priori concepts should precede
empirical knowledge of objects. For since a mere modification of our sensibility
can never be met with outside us, the objects, as appearances, constitute an
object which is merely in us" (A 128 f, and correspondingly in B 163 f).
With
this, the objectivity of the pure concepts (cf. A 85, 93), which Kant thinks he
has demonstrated, proves to be in fact a "subjective objectivity."
Obviously this
transcendental idealism is the direct result of a thetic interpretation of
knowledge. In B xiii f, Kant speaks of a "questioning" and a
"seeking" on the part of reason 11,
so that he leaves room for the recognition that the experiment has a real
function in the scientist's procedures (and thus in human knowledge). But the
final result of the Transcendental Deduction (the heart of the KrV) recognizes
only the creative moment of the understanding. It leaves aside the moment of
critical reflection on this prior act of understanding (the insight) and thus on
the projected, hypothetical explanation of the data. It leaves aside the moment
of verification, which in natural science takes the form of an experiment. The
absence of this critical and verifying moment is connected with the tendency in
the "Critique of Pure Reason", which Vaihinger also notes, to erase
the difference between concept and judgment. 12
This in turn should be seen in connection with the fact that Kant attributes
only a regulative function to our cognitive dynamism that tends toward the
unconditioned (B xx f). As result, while he indeed speaks of judgment, he does
not grasp its defining characteristic, which is the absolute positing (affirmation) of an intelligible 13.
In fact, when we assert in the judgment: "Yes, it is so," we rule out
the contradictory assertion.
5. Knowledge
of Particular Laws — An Unresolved Problem
The
"Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding"
explains definitively, at least at first sight, the origin of the laws of nature
and, more generally, the intelligible component of human knowledge. The thesis
that the subject brings to the "raw material of the sensible
impressions" (B 1) the intelligible component of things, which is the
"combination" (B 129: "Verbindung")
of those impressions, as an "addition" (B 1: "Zusatz"), together with the thesis that "we can know a
priori 14
of things only what we ourselves put into them" (B xviii), amounts to the thesis that the laws of
nature are the product of a legislative activity of the understanding (cf. A
126).
But shortly after repeating
this epistemological-metaphysical position, according to which "categories
are concepts which prescribe laws a
priori to appearances, and therefore to nature" (B 163), Kant continues
by unexpectedly writing:
"Pure
understanding is not, however, in a position, through mere categories, to
prescribe to appearances any a priori laws
other than those which are involved in a nature in general, that is, in the
conformity to law of all appearances in space and time. Special
[besondere] laws, as concerning those appearances which are empirically
determined, cannot in their specific character be derived from categories,
although they are one and all subject to them. To obtain any knowledge
whatsoever of these special laws, we must resort to experience" (B 165).
How
can he so unexpectedly place this restriction on the legislative activity of the
understanding, when previously in the Transcendental Deduction not a word has
been said about it? The reason is twofold:
First, Kant's profoundly
realist attitude, which pushes through again and again in the "Critique of
Pure Reason", and because of which he was never able to accept completely
the idealism to which the premises of his theory of knowledge logically lead 15.
Second, the experimental character of natural science. If namely the scientist
completely prescribes laws to nature, there is no longer a place in his
procedures for the experiment. Kant wishes to limit legislation by the
understanding to "nature in general" (B 165), "experience in
general" (A 125), "pure laws" (A 128), "a
priori laws" (B 165), "highest laws" (A 126), "original
laws" (A 216), "transcendental laws" (ibid.), "principles of
pure understanding" (A 148). All of these expressions are burdened with the
imprecision of Kant's a priori elements of
the understanding, especially with regard to the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori.
Furthermore, the question
arises: What laws is Kant thinking of when, in evident distinction from the
"transcendental" laws, he speaks in B 165 of "special laws"?
In the parallel passage in A 127 and in the "Prolegomena" (IV 320)
these latter laws are even called "empirical
laws." Now, the restriction of the domain of the legislative activity of
the understanding that Kant speaks of concerns the formal constitutive component
of objects, not their individuality. The reference to sensible experience is
enough to explain the latter. The special laws at issue are the various laws of
nature, e.g., the laws discovered by Galilei, Torricelli, and Stahl (B xii f),
and therefore are universal laws!
Now, for these laws the
principle of B 4 holds, which Kant repeats in this context in the following
words: "The universal laws of nature can and must be known a
priori (that is, independently of all experience)" (Prolegomena, IV
319). There is no doubt that the basic tendency of the transcendental philosophy
is to say that "every determination of the sensible manifold is deduced
from the synthetic functions and from their relation to the unity of
apperception." 16
It cannot escape someone
who considers the matter carefully that here Kant not only has restricted the
legislative activity of the transcendental subject, but has eliminated it
altogether. He observes that a similar problem arises for the
"inexhaustible multiplicity of appearances" in relation to the
"pure form of sensible intuition" (A 127). But with this observation
Kant is far from resolving the difficulty of how universal forms and concepts
are explained by recourse to experience. Rather, after he has said that all
order, every formal element, is the work of the understanding, he now is
recognizing that the same difficulty existed already in the Transcendental
Aesthetic, where space and time are a priori
forms of the sensibility.
At this point Kant's
position halfway between realism and idealism breaks down. This has been noted
by several authors. Paulsen's observations are particularly instructive. He
refers especially to Kant's saying in § 15 that all combination (Verbindung)
is an act of the understanding (B 129 f). He then continues: "How is it -
unexpectedly - necessary that experience must intervene in order to know special
laws? Is it possible to draw from experience laws whose source in our knowledge
would not be the understanding? In that case, there would be combinations of
appearances according to rules which would derive from the receptivity of
sense" 17.
There is no reply in Kant
to this objection, which touches the nerve of the entire transcendental
philosophy. On the one hand, he asserts that a form can originate only from the
subject, while on the other hand he asserts that experience is necessary in
order to reach a knowledge of the specific forms that constitute the whole of
nature. These two assertions, which contradict each other, are simply placed
side by side. In particular, Kant does not explain anywhere how the
understanding and the sensibility cooperate in the knowledge of the same
reality.
Everything leads us to
think that Kant was aware that what he had presented in the Transcendental
Deduction of the categories was not really a valid answer to how we come to know
the various laws of nature. In fact, he returned to the same problem later and
looked for other ways to solve it 18.
Already in the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic (A 642-668) under the
heading "The Regulative Employment of the Ideas of Pure Reason" we
find a first, and different, attempt in connection with the three logical
principles of homogeneity, specification, and continuity of forms (A 658). But,
since the treatment of the "principle of specification" is really
about the systematic ordering of all the empirical laws of nature, the problem
of how we come to know these laws and what their ontological status is stays in
the background.
The publication of the
"Critique of Judgment" in 1790 offered Kant the chance to try again to
bridge the gap between "the universal laws without which nature cannot be
thought" and the multiplicity of special laws (V 182). Sections IV, V, and
VIII of the Introduction touch on this problem. The means that Kant uses here is
the "reflective judgment" [reflektierende
Urteilskraft: V 179]. Here the "put into" (B xiv) and the
"prescribing" (B 159) of the First Critique receive a strange
reinterpretation: The reflective judgment looks for special laws "as if [als
ob] an understanding (even if not our own) had established them for the
benefit of our cognitive faculties, so as to make possible a system of
experience according to particular laws of nature" (Introduction., Sect.
IV: V 180). The success of this search is due neither to the legislative
activity of the understanding (which is limited to "universal" laws)
nor to an insight into data that critical reflection would then confirm. It is
due to an "incomprehensible lucky fact," 19
the lucky encounter of an extrascientific hypothesis (the "as if [als
ob] of a superhuman understanding) with the scientist's search (cf. V 184).
But it seems that Kant was
not satisfied with this solution either, as appears from the repeated attempts
in the "Opus Postumum" to find a "transition [Übergang]
from the metaphysical principles of natural science to physics" (XXI 174),
and thus to achieve "the realization of the transcendental
philosophy," as G. Lehmann expressed it in his Introduction to the Academy
edition of the "Opus Postumum" (XXII 752). In a series of studies
Lehmann has come to the conclusion that the Transcendental Deduction of the
categories, and thus the interpretation of the understanding as a legislator
over nature, has failed.
P. Plaass also concluded
that the attempt to bring the pure part of natural science into agreement with
the empirical part "consumed in the 'Opus Postumum' the last of Kant's
strength, but without succeeding." 20
Indeed, we have a late confession from Kant himself. Writing to Christian Garve
on September 21, 1798 and to Johann Kiesewetter a month later, he recognized
that in his search for a transition from the "metaphysical principles of
natural science to physics" a gap still remained "in the system of the
critical philosophy." (XII 257 and 258)
In his Introduction to the
Microfiche-Edition of the "Opus postumum" Reinhard Brandt emphasizes
that Kant's thought in this writing, far from taking stock of his life-long
achievement, was still in movement and progress. Though more than 70 years old
he dared to break new territory, indeed a new philosophical world-system 21.
In view of the fact, that the problem of a "transition" arose out of
the duality, nay disparateness of sense and intellect underlying the
"Critique of Pure Reasson", and in view of Kant's failure to find the
missing link, as the philosopher himself was forced to admit, I cannot but see
Brandt's intepretation and glorification of him as a downright "escamotage".
In this unfinished work Kant was not at all trying to climb to a new
philosophical peak; he rather wanted to find the overdue remedy to his
epistemological-metaphysical position in which he had just drawn Rationalism and
Empiricism near, without overcoming their shortcomings into a single coherent
system that would highlight how sense and intellect collaborate towards human
kowing of reality. Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason" represents a
moment in the long process, which led at last to distinguish philosophy and
natural science, so that natural science itself determines its own basic
concepts and principles without borrowing them from a higher science named
metaphysics. This does not deny, however, that philosophy could and should
reflect upon what the scientist is doing, when he is working as a scientist, in
order to bring the scientific method back to the transcendental structure of our
cognitive intentionality.
6. Beyond
the Impasse 22
Kant
believed he had noticed a gap in the laws of nature between universal and
therefore (according to him) a priori laws,
and special or particular (but still universal!) laws, which he called empirical. But in presenting it he actually spotlighted a basic gap
in the "Critique of Pure Reason" itself. It is the gap between the
sensibility, which alone - according to the "Critique of Pure Reason"
- is able to establish cognitive contact with reality, and the understanding
which, though intelligent and rational, is not by itself cognitive. This split
between sensibility and understanding led Kant to construct two worlds: a) The
real world to which sense has access. But in fact Kant is not prepared to adopt
naVve realism without reservation; his "real" world has for man the
character of a world of appearances, b) The merely thought world of the idealist
tradition.
But just as Kant was not
prepared to accept naVve realism fully, he also was not prepared to accept fully
the world of idealism. Consequently, he cut short the logical implications of
the two disparate premises (principles) on which the "Critique of Pure
Reason" rests when, in his interpretation of experimental science, he was
confronted with particular laws. These were no longer conceived as a
priori, a product of the understanding by means of the so-called
transcendental laws. He therefore was forced to set aside the first of his two
principles, namely the principle that universality is a "sure criterion of a
priori knowledge" (B 4). These particular laws were conceived as
empirical, since here the sensibility gives a further determination to "the
pure laws of understanding" (A 127 f). This contradicts the second
principle, namely that sense is never a source of truly universal knowledge (B
3).
To introduce here an
"application" of the understanding, with its transcendental laws, to
the manifold provided by the sensibility would be to introduce an ad
hoc solution whose premises are lacking in the "Critique of Pure
Reason". If a solution is possible, it must be found at the very start of
the inquiry where Kant introduces the "two stems of human knowledge,
namely, sensibility and understanding" (A 15). How are these two faculties
related to one another? Kant recognizes that "thought" and thus the
understanding "must relate ultimately to intuitions" (A 19), and thus
to the sensibility. But this faculty by itself is not able to come into relation
with reality; it can only work out what sense provides to it, using categories
of its own to which no reality corresponds. From this impasse are derived the
two distinct streams of sensist realism and idealism of which I spoke above, and
which Kant only later tried to reunite by interrupting their logical course at
the stage of the so-called empirical laws of nature. We have seen how Kant
struggled with this problem for years, without success.
In my opinion, the impasse
can be overcome only by re-examining some of the fundamental premises of the
"Critique of Pure Reason".
First, we must recognize
that the relation of the knowing subject to reality as something to be known is
given not in sense intuition, but in the unlimited intelligent and rational
dynamism of the human spirit.
Second, we must recognize
that this dynamism is functionally connected to the sensibility 23,
so that it cannot pose its questions for intelligence without referring to the
data provided by experience, and it cannot answer the critical question about
the correctness of the intelligible grasped in the data except by turning to
them again.
Third, and as a conclusion
from the two preceding premises, what has been said about the intentional
dynamism and the triadic structure of the cognitional process can explain, in a
way that is verifiable by introspection, the scientist's procedure that Kant
refers to with his metaphor of the judge. The scientist asks questions about the
data of experience, questions formulated with the intellectual means appropriate
for his purpose. The answer to the question for intelligence adds
an intelligible element that was not present at the level of the content of the
sensibility. In this sense there is a moment that can properly be described as a
"putting into." As a result of this putting into, the scientist thinks
of a definite reality or event in nature, and the judge thinks of a definite
legal fact.
But thinking, planning,
projecting, is not yet knowing. Here there intervenes the reflective and
critical moment that occurs in all human knowledge of reality and that in
natural science takes the specific form of the experiment. Only if the
experiment gives a positive result, so that the explanatory hypothesis is
confirmed, does the scientist arrive at knowledge of reality 24.
Only then is it possible to say that the intelligible that the understanding has
added to the content of the sense experience
actually has been discovered in that content, and therefore is a formal component of
reality. In Kant, the absence of a clear distinction between the moment of
searching for an intelligibility and the moment of truth keeps him from doing
justice both to the creative moment of understanding, where he takes as
definitive what is only hypothetical, and to the reflective moment, where he
makes the experiment superfluous. (If reality is the product of the knowing
subject, there is no point in asking about the truth of what the subject has put
into the appearance furnished by sense!).
† [Originally published in Universitas Monthly Review of Philosophy And Culture, n. 357 (vol. 31, n. 2) February 2004, pp. 13-35, and now published as an Internet edition with the author’s permission. Donald E. Buzzelli of Washington, D.C. translated the original Italian into English to prepare it for publication]
1 Cf. Kant's letter to Johann Bernoulli, October 16, 1781. Quotations in Roman numerals followed by Arabic numerals refer to volume and page numbers in the Academy edition of the works of Kant. But quotations to the "Critique of Pure Reason" refer to page numbers in the A or in the B original editions. Quotations from the "Critique of Pure Reason" will employ the Norman Kemp Smith translation with my emphases.
2 In the article "Erfinder und Entdecker oder Richter der Natur? Die Kantische Richter-Metapher und die Selbstlosigkeit der modernen Naturwissenschaften" in: Zeitschrift fur philosophische Forschung 43 (1989) 32-57, Werner Kutschmann examined the metaphor of the judge in order to see to what extent it is able to express the role of the scientist in science, as that is conceived today. In fact, science today wishes to dominate nature much more than it wishes to express an impartial judgment about it. Such an employment of the metaphor does not fall within the scope of my present article, which is meant to concentrate on the significance of the metaphor for the theory of knowledge and for metaphysics.
3 Kant believes he has grasped the procedures of modern scientists with this principle, and expresses it several times in pregnant formulae. Cf. in Hermann Schmitz, Was wollte Kant?, Bonn 1989, 345-347, a series of passages with this sense, together with reflections on Vico's principle, "Verum est factum"."
4 Peter Plaass, Kants Theorie der Naturwissenschaft. Eine Untersuchung zur Vorrede von Kants "Metaphysischen Anfangsgründen der Naturwissenschaft", Gottingen 1965, 119. Plaass repeats without any objection Kant's equating of "putting into" with "questioning." The purpose of my reflections is to show that "questioning," with its a priori element, is not at all the same as "putting into." Or, better, that "putting into" with a view to a "questioning" has a different meaning from what Kant obviously intends in his "Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of Understanding." There he says that the "connection and unity of appearances [a result of the legislative activity of the understanding] (in the representation of an object) are to be met with only in ourselves." (A 130)
5 Here Kant simplifies the pupil's task in order to bring out the contrast with the way the judge proceeds. Although the pupil is not engaged in formal inquiry, his learning still is not a wholly passive process.
6 The use of the term " Vorverständnis" depends on the fact that since Dilthey the distinction has been made between comprehending (Verstehen), which refers to the human world, and explaining (Erklären), which refers to nature. Though it has a justification, this distinction should not lead us to overlook the fact that both in the so-called "Geisteswissenschaften" and in natural science, knowledge of reality does not occur in the "comprehending" or in the "explaining," since both are instances of "understanding," but in the subsequent moment of judging. Consequently, one should say that human knowledge consists of a threefold structure of experience, understanding (either Verstehen or Erklären), and judgment.
7 For a more detailed examination, I refer to my earlier study: "Kants Lehre von der menschlichen Erkenntnis: eine sensualistische Version des Intuitionismus," in Theologie und Philosophie 57 (1982) 202-224, 321-347; and "Intentionalität contra Intuition," ibid., 59 (1984) 249-264. English version in G Sala, Lonergan and Kant. Five Essays on Human Knowledge, translated by J. Spoerl, University of Toronto Press 1994, 41-101.
8 Kant's faculty of reason (Vernunft), with its transcendental ideas, is also a part of Denken. These ideas also are a priori, but we can prescind from them here, since they have only a regulative, i.e., systematizing, function with respect to the knowledge of objects that we have already obtained by the joint operation of sense and intellect.
9 Hans Vaihinger, Kommentar zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Stuttgart 1891, I 393. The problem comes from two opposing facts. More precisely, it comes from what Kant considered to be a fact, i.e., that we possess a priori knowledge of objects (his rationalistic premise), and the fact that we have knowledge of reality (his realist premise).
11 The question, as a question, does not posit anything definitively, but only seeks. The answer to this question posits in the data an intelligible that may be a component of the reality that one is seeking.
13 For Kant, judgment is conceived as the relation of the subject to a predicate (A 6). But grasping that a certain intelligible predicate possibly belongs to a subject is still part of the moment of understanding, since an insight is always a grasping of connections among data or among concepts. Now, since Kant defines judgment as a relation, he establishes, consequently, a perfect correspondence between the supreme concepts, the categories (A 80) - a concept expresses in fact a relation - and the supreme forms of the judgment (A 70).
14 But why must there be a priori knowledge? The reason is that for Kant any knowledge that is universal and necessary can only be a priori. Cf. B 4.
15 The "thing in itself ("Ding an sich") plays a fundamental role in Kant: Without it the "Critique of Pure Reason" would be totally incomprehensible. Things in themselves (though unknowable to us!) exist, act on our senses, are manifold, have properties parallel to those of the appearances, etc. A passage in which realism emerges quite clearly is found in A 477-480. Kant distinguishes the domains of knowledge (transcendental philosophy, mathematics, morals) in which no question occurs that we could not answer, "since the object is not to be met with outside the concept," from the domain of "natural science", in which "the natural appearances are objects which are given to us independently of our concepts, and the key to them lies not in us and our pure thinking, but outside us."
16 Benno Erdmann, "Kritik der Problemlage in Kants transzendentaler Deduktion der Kategorien," in: Sitzungsberichte der Konigl. Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Berlin 1915, 217.
18 A detailed examination of what I can only mention here is found in my article: "Ein experimentum crucis der Transzendentalphilosophie Kants: Die Erkenntnis des Besonderen", in: Im Ringen um die Wahrheit (Festschrift für Alma von Stockhausen), Remigius Bäumer u.a. (Hrsg.), Weilheim-Bierbronnen: Gustav-Siewerth-Akademie 1997, 111-126.
19 Thus Wilhelm Windelband in his Introduction to the "Critique of Judgment" in the Academy edition" (V 521).
21 Immanuel Kant, Opus postumum, Staatsbibliothek zu Berlin - Preußischer Kulturbesitz, Berlin 1999, 11.
22 In these concluding reflections I am referring to the volume by Bernard Lonergan, Insight. A Study of Human Understanding, London 1957; University of Toronto Press (Collected Works of B.L., 3) 51992. An excellent summary of the theory of knowledge presented there is the same author's article "Cognitional Structure," in Collection (Collected Works of B.L., 4), 1988, 205-221.
23 For St. Thomas Aquinas the human understanding is by its nature "conversus ad phantasma [turned toward the phantasm]," i.e., toward the sensibility (Summa Theol. I, q.84, a.7 with reference to Aristotlés De anima III, 7). Thus it appears that the transition between the understanding and the sensibility that Kant vainly searched for, a) is made possible by this constitutive orientation of the human understanding, which is a faculty of a substance composed of spirit and matter, and b) in fact occurs every time we understand something, since our act of understanding is an "intelligere in sensibili [understanding in the sensible]" (which Aristotle in the cited place calls "noein en tois phantasmasi"). This "intelligere in sensibili" serves as a hinge connecting the content of the sensation with the concept produced by the understanding. Every human concept therefore is sensible and intellectual at the same time, since understanding is the act that mediates between the concrete and the abstract, between the singular and the universal.
24 In this brief description of the experiment I prescind from the correct (!) objection that the experiment, if conceived this way, provides no valid proof. It is namely an invalid form of the simple hypothetical argument: If p, then q; but q; therefore p. Owing to this reason the epistemic status of experiential science is, on principle, that of an hypothesis. But as a matter of fact a scientific hypothesis gets nearer to truth with greater number and variety of experiments that conform to the hypothesis.