The
Concept of the Transcendental in Kant and Lonergan
by
Giovanni Sala, S.J.
To
speak of the “transcendental” today is to refer, like it or not, to Kant,
and in particular to his “Critique of Pure Reason” (the “Critique”).
In the Introduction to this work he speaks of a “transcendental
knowledge”, which is occupied “not so much with objects as with the mode of
our knowledge of objects is so far as this mode of knowledge is to be possible a
priori.” The term “transcendental” is so important for Kant that he
called his thought “transcendental philosophy” (B 25).
He took this term from the Scholastic tradition and gave it a meaning of
his own.
1.
The medieval Scholastics called the predicates of being as being, communissima
or prima. These
predicates were considered valid for any reality.
In this they differed from categorial predicates, which were each valid
only for a particular category, i.e., for one of the highest genera into which
reality can be divided. Only later
in that tradition did it become customary to call a being transcendens,
insofar as it goes beyond every categorial limit, and to call the corresponding
predicates transcendentalia. The
number of such predicates was somewhat variable, but they always included unum,
verum and bonum.
2.
What led Kant to introduce the expression “transcendental knowledge” to
refer to his new theory of knowledge? His
reason is given at the beginning of the Introduction. Our knowledge is characterized by the features of
universality and necessity, which can not be explained by the receptivity of
sense. Sense indeed tells us that
an individual thing is thus and so, but it does not tell us that this thing can
exist identically in innumerable cases. Sense
tells us that a thing exists and an event occurs, but it does not tell us that
they must exist or occur. Therefore,
Kant concludes, universality and necessity are sure signs of an a priori
knowledge and are inseparable from one another (B 3f).
“A priori knowledge” means an item of knowledge or an aspect
of one that is “added” by our understanding.
In this way Kant has already set up his conception of human knowing as a
binary structure consisting of “intuitions” (Anschauungen) of sense
and concepts of the understanding (cf. A 50-52).
2.1
A modern reader of the Critique will be surprised that Kant can pass so
easily from features of knowledge that are not explainable in terms of sense to
the affirmation that these features are added (B 1) by the understanding,
in the sense that the understanding draws them out of itself.
He never considers the hypothesis that the understanding can add these
features because it is able to discover in the data of sense an intelligible
component that the data bear but the senses cannot access.
There are two reasons for this oversight: a) Kant conceives knowing
simply as a dynamism of extroversion on the model of the faculty of sight. Knowing is “seeing” what stands in front of the subject
as distinct from that subject. In
other words, the known is an ob-jectum, a Gegen-stand.
b) Kant does not acknowledge in the human understanding a capacity to
intuit. The only intuition of which
man is capable is that of the senses, which are all dynamisms of extroversion.
This means that in us only the sensibility is properly a cognitive
faculty, since it alone is able to “see” and thus to build the bridge that
brings the subject into a cognitive relation with the object.
But
Kant is not an empiricist à la Hume. While
he accepts the conception of sense as the only faculty that properly knows, he
refuses to reduce human knowledge to sense alone.
The whole “Critique” is an extremely acute effort to recover for the
intellect its role in human knowing. The
price of this undertaking is to make the intellect “the author of
experience” (B 127) in the sense that it is the creator of a reality of its
own—the reality of appearances—while at the same time recognizing the
existence of a reality in itself (the “thing in itself”) that is entirely
unknowable to us. This is the
quintessence of the “Critique” and is contained in nuce in the first
two paragraphs of the Transcendental Aesthetic (B 33f).
There Kant asserts that the sense “sees” while the understanding
elaborates (cf. B 1) what the sense presents to it.
Two
themes are present in the “Critique”. There
is the sensist theme connected with intuitionism: knowing is seeing, but the
only seeing we are capable of is that of sense.
There is the transcendental-idealist theme that attributes to the
understanding the function of introducing into the “appearances” provided by
sense an intelligible order, the order that science is gradually discovering.
These two components are brought together as infrastructure and
superstructure, but without constituting an intrinsic unity namely a unity in
which the act of intellect takes
over, but at the same time overcomes the sense cognitively and ontologically.
The absence of the “missing link” between sense and understanding is
at the origin of the obvious dualism that marks all of Kant’s thought.
2.2
How did Kant think he could identify the a priori “additions” made by
the understanding? Through the
“transcendental knowledge” that is occupied with “the mode of our
knowledge of objects in so far as this mode of knowledge is to be possible a
priori” (B 25). Does this
mean through his so-called “turn to the subject”?
Yes, but with a clarification or, rather, with a restriction.
His reflection on the subject takes place from the standpoint of the
object, about which Kant claims to know already both its qualifying features
and the fact that these features arise out of the subject.
This means that Kant will discern in the subject
that, and only that, which he
considers necessary in order to explain the object as thus conceived.
Hence it is not decisive for Kant whether or not introspection succeeds
in identifying in the subject the elements he postulates.
They must be there anyway, since they characterize the object and
cannot be derived from experience.
To
the question of what the a priori elements are that the understanding
possesses, Kant has a ready answer. For
him the faculty of thinking with concepts and the faculty of judging are in
reality identical (A 69). Now the
task of understanding by means of concepts is to perform a “combination” (Verbindung)
or “synthesis” of the manifold provided by sense (B § 15).
Consequently, there will be as many of these syntheses as there are
logical functions of our judgments. For
Kant, in fact, a judgment consists in a relation (and hence a synthesis) of
subject and predicate. Drawing on
the tables of judgments that then were current in manuals of logic, and adapting
them for his own purpose, Kant presents in the “Critique” the “complete”
table (A 79f) of all our a priori syntheses and thus of all the basic
intelligibles with which our understanding is endowed.
These are his twelve categories, among which are “totality”
(multiplicity as unity) and “necessity”.
The first few pages of the Preface to the Second Edition contain an
important discussion of the function of these intelligibles in constituting
human knowledge.
Mathematicians
since antiquity and students of nature in the modern era have entered upon
“the sure path of science” thanks to a “revolution” in thinking (B xi):
“They learned that reason has insight only into that which it produces
after a plan of its own, … [and thus it] must itself show the way with
principles of judgment based upon fixed laws, constraining nature to give answer
to questions of reason’s own determining” (B xiii, emphasis added).
In this interpretation of science, which is repeated with various
formulations, two directions can be distinguished.
In the first direction, which we can call anticipatory-hypothetical,
reason “seeks”, “learns” and above all “asks”.
In the other direction, which we can call anticipatory-creative, reason
“produces” intelligibility and “places it within” the manifold provided
by sense. In the end, the second
direction prevails, i.e., the thetic [constructive] interpretation of the
activity of the understanding, which thereby annuls the experimental moment that
Kant recognized as constitutive of modern science.
That the Kantian a priori has this function is shown beyond any
possible ambiguity in the section on the “Transcendental Deduction of the Pure
Concepts of Understanding” that has the understanding “prescribing laws to
nature” (B 159) so that the objects it knows are a mere “modification of our
sensibility”, “determinations of my identical self” (A 129).
The
tension between these two ways of conceiving the a priori of the
understanding is particularly manifest in the metaphor of the judge (B xiiif),
which Kant uses to illustrate the procedures of science.
The judge puts questions to the witnesses and requires them to answer.
He is concerned with facts in the light of the code of law. His questions are meant to bring out from what the witnesses
say elements that will allow him to frame a juridical hypothesis about what
happened. In this sense he adds
to the pure data of common-sense knowledge an intelligible that makes a
juridical reality out of them. But
this addition, at first, is only hypothetical.
Only in the subsequent reflective-critical stage does he resolve for
himself whether the meaning he has added is the discovery of a formal
element that makes out of the data a juridical reality, or whether instead it is
an intelligibility that is not adequate to what actually happened and therefore
is not sufficient for an objectively grounded decision.
This
example shows that the key element in knowing any reality is the question.
Not just any question, but one that is relevant to that reality.
A question arises out of a prior knowledge of the reality one is
asking about, and thus it involves a cognitive a priori.
But this a priori is only relative. The pre-knowledge that enables the person of common sense or
the scientist to ask a question is that person’s prior familiarity with a
certain range of reality, or acquired through some ad hoc study.
But how is it possible to acquire this pre-knowledge of a range of
reality, if one learns only by asking questions relevant to that very question?
There would seem to be an infinite regress, with every question requiring
some pre-knowledge that is obtained by answering a previous question, which
would preclude asking any questions at all.
We will see this when we examine Lonergan’s conception of the
transcendental. Here let it suffice
to observe that the question does not introduce anything into the reality
to be known; on the contrary, it opens up for the questioner the possibility of
grasping the reality as it is. The
question aims at adding (!) an intelligibility to the data provided by
experience, thus providing the basis for posing the further critical
question “Is it really so?” One
thereby moves on to the judgment, in which the object that was experienced and
then was understood is known for the first time in its status as a reality.
2.3
The other feature of our knowledge is necessity.
What first strikes us is that Kant places necessity, together with
reality (existence) and possibility, among the categories.
In fact, as Kant recognizes, these three categories do not add any
intelligibility to the content of experiece.
Rather, they are predicates that determine the object not in itself, but
in its relation to our faculty of knowing: more precisely, in its relation - for
Kant - to the sensibility. This
reveals in the clearest fashion Kant’s sensualism, which is a philosophically
ennobled form of the naïve realism according to which we know real things
because we see them, touch them, etc. For
Kant the possible, real, and necessary are three different ways in which the
object of thought is connected (directly or mediately) with a possible, actual,
or necessary experience. Necessary
experience is illustrated by effects in relation to their cause and also by a
(non-free) cause in relation to its effects.
3.
Lonergan sets up his study of human knowledge without restrictions: he does not
ask about the object of knowledge, much less about specific features of the
object that are supposed to be already known.
He asks simply: “What operations do we perform when we know?”
Whether these operations have an object, what it is, and what sort of
truth value it has, are questions he will be able to answer only after he has
examined the individual operations in themselves.
In brief, he takes as his object the
subject as a subject that is conscious owing to the psychic acts of
knowing that he is performing.
To
reflect on one’s own internal experience is to make use of an empirical
method. This method is unlike
that of natural science in that it starts out from our internal experience
(consciousness) rather than from the external experience of the senses.
It is therefore a generalized empirical method.
With it, we are able to arrive at verifiable affirmations about our
cognitive operations.
3.1
Objectifying the questions with which the
intellectual phase of human knowing begins leads us to recognize that our
cognitive dynamism operates in two distinct stages.
The first is introduced by the question for understanding, “what is
it?”, directed at the content of experience.
This question leads to an inquiry that aims to discover an intelligible
content that the senses bring to us even though it is not within their power to
know it.
This
intelligible always consists in a relation among the data of experience.
Here arises the fundamental distinction between common sense and science.
Common sense considers the data in their relation to the knowing subject,
as a being endowed with senses (color, sound, dimensions, etc.), or in their
“existential” relevance. Science
considers the data in their mutual interrelations in order to grasp the
intelligibility immanent in them. In
this respect the “synthesis” is confirmed that Kant speaks of in connection
with our concepts (B § 15). But
something much different must be said about a synthesis that supposedly already
exists in the subject and is only waiting to be introduced into the object.
Inquiry
is followed by understanding, i.e., grasping an intelligible in the
sensible. Owing to what it has
understood the intellect is able to form (intelligently!) an inner word, the concept,
and then also the outer spoken word.
The concept expresses the intelligible grasped in the sensible together
with that part or aspect of the sensible that is relevant to that intelligible
(since it is the intelligible of a sensible!).
The intellect can grasp an intelligible only in a concrete
sensible provided by experience. But
the concept that expresses it is by its nature universal.
Just as the intelligible is found to be present in these data, it
can be present in innumerable other cases.
We speak of “a house”, “a hydrogen atom”, “a storm”, etc.
What we mean is not limited to the individual we are considering.
This
applies to the experience of a schoolboy who a) grasps the intelligibility of
the circle by fixing his attention on the figure his teacher has drawn on the
blackboard (with the aid of the teacher’s explanations!), and b) then
pronounces the Euclidean definition of the circle, which is valid for any circle
regardless of its size, the material it is made of, the time when it exists,
etc.
In
this way Lonergan has explained the universality of the concept without
having recourse to any a priori synthesis. The act from which the concept emanates is the intelligere
in sensibili that stands at the center of the Thomist theory of knowledge.
Thomas took it over from the noein en tois phantasmasi of the De
Anima (III, 6-8), by which Aristotle had overcome the impasse of the
Platonic ideas. That act is so far
from esoteric that St. Thomas could write: “Hoc quilibet in seipso experiri
potest” (Summa theol. I, q.84, a.7)—anyone can experience it in
himself.
In
Kant’s thought the act of understanding remained terra ignota.
Historically, the reason for this is that he was in a conceptualist
tradition that goes back at least to Duns Scotus.
Scotus had denied the intelligere in phantasmate of Aristotle and
had explained the universality of the concept in terms of an unconscious
abstractive process performed by an intellect conceived as a kind of abstracting
machine. Only after the concept has
been formed does the properly conscious activity of the intellect begin for
Scotus, and this consists in grasping the relation among concepts already
present (intelligere in conceptibus).
Kant took over Scotus’s intuitionist conception of human knowing, but
since he had dropped the Scotist tradition’s idea of abstraction and did not
recognize the act that connects the intellect with sense experience, he had
recourse to the alternative of twelve a priori concepts.
The
position taken in this paper regarding the concept can be summarized in the
following statements. A priori
concepts do not exist. The concept
is one of the products of the cognitive process, resulting from the
collaboration of sense and intellect. Every
concept therefore is at once empirical and intellectual. Purely empirical concepts do not exist. They would be a mere flatus vocis.
3.2
The same introspective analysis also permits Lonergan to explain the necessity
that characterizes our knowledge. But
for Lonergan one cannot speak of necessity in knowledge without going beyond the
stage of our cognitional structure that ends with the concept.
Once we have arrived at a thought of a determinate object, our dynamism,
being rational, poses a second question that startes the
reflective-critical phase: “Is it (i.e., the object of experience) really so
(i.e., the way I think it in the concept)?”
The thought object expresses an intelligible that requires a
corresponding sensible in experience, and we can know that that object exists
only if the corresponding sensible is there.
The reflection that follows this second question is intended to find out
whether at the level of experience all the data corresponding to the
intelligible are there, and no data exist that could call into question the
correctness of the understanding from which the concept
proceeded. In other words, it is a matter of finding out whether the
preceding intelligere is correct. To
grasp that correctness is to grasp the reason (the so-called evidence) that
permits our mind to reply with a
“yes”, “est”, to its critical question and so to affirm
(to posit) unconditionally what previously it only thought.
But
an unconditioned affirmation requires unconditioned grounds.
That is what the reflective intellect grasps.
The conditioned is
the object thought inasmuch as it
is a finite intelligible. The conditions
are the data of experience inasmuch as these data actually stand in the relation
expressed by that intelligible. They
thereby satisfy, within the structure of reflection, the conditions of
that conditioned. The conditioned
thus is equivalent to a virtually unconditioned that is capable of
justifying the judgment “It is so”. But
the grounded affirmation that a thing is, is the same as knowledge that the
thing exists. The being of the
affirmation (intentional being) is the means by which we attain knowledge of the
being of things (real being). Ens
iudicio vero cognoscitur.
From
this analysis of the third phase in the structure of the cognitive process we
see that the (direct or indirect) contribution of experience is indispensable if
we are to know being. This indispensability is not to be taken in the sense of
Kantian sensism, but because experience within reflection fulfils the function
of satisfying the conditions of the conditioned.
The same analysis also permits us to clarify what kind of necessity
characterizes our knowledge. It is not absolute necessity, but the necessity of the
contingent, i.e., of that which is not being itself but which, as
intelligible, can exist and in fact does exist. It is the necessity of contingent being.
3.3
There is a further aspect of Kant’s “transcendental knowledge” that
deserves attention. The part of the
“Critique” that deals with the intellectual phase of knowledge is titled the
“Transcendental Logic”. Indeed,
the reflections he makes there do not go beyond the limits of logic.
Logic is concerned with formal relations within knowledge, concentrating
on the end products of the cognitive activity that moves from experience to the
concept. The adjective transcendental,
in turn, means that these formal elements of knowledge are constitutive of the
object. The performative aspect of our intentionality, which starts
out from a question, is left out of an inquiry that centers on the contents that
enter into an object. Contents such
as the intuitions of the sensibility, the categories of the understanding, up to
the “I think”, the synthetic-originary unity of apperception (B 131-135)
that is the highest point of reference in the whole logical mechanism devised to
explain the formal aspects of “reality”.
Formulating
the issue in these logical terms hindered Kant from recognizing the
contradiction that undermines his entire theory of knowledge
With his “Critique” he is telling the reader that we do not know
reality, but only the appearance of something unknown.
Such a thesis does not imply any contradiction.
But a contradiction comes to light as soon as someone (Kant!) asserts
this conception of knowledge. He
is saying that really and truly we do not know what really and truly is so. This is a contradiction between the content of the
assertion and the performance (Vollzug) of that same assertion.
The transcendental conditions of possibility within transcendental logic
do not transcend that logic. It
seems entirely justified to say that Kant’s turn to the subject stopped
halfway: it was the turn to a subject gravely mutilated in its intelligent and
rational subjectivity.
Giovanni. Sala SJ, Hochschule für Philosophie, Munich, March 1, 2008.